Why does there not exist a particular finite set of congruences that forms a partition of the set of integers












1














There is a paragragh that I saw in an article and could not really understand. The article is Covering Systems of Congruences, J. Fabrykowski and T. Smotzer, Mathematics Magazine Vol. 78, No. 3 (Jun., 2005), pp. 228-231, DOI: 10.2307/30044163. It starts by discussing problem 9 from the 2002 American Invitational Mathematics Examination (AIME):




PROBLEM. Harold, Tanya, and Ulysses paint a very long fence. Harold starts with the first picket and paints every $h$th picket; Tanya starts with the second picket and paints every $t$th picket; and Ulysses starts with the third picket and paints every $u$th picket. If every picket gets painted exactly once, find all possible triples $(h,t,u)$.




After presenting the solution, the article goes on to say:




One can generalize the AIME problem and ask whether there exists a finite set of congruences, with all moduli distinct and greater than or equal to $2$, that forms a partition of the set of integers. This turns out to be impossible. Relaxing the assumption about partitioning the integers, one can look for finite sets of congruences such that every integer belongs to at least one of them."




Can anyone help explain why the first part is impossible?










share|cite|improve this question
























  • By the way, if you have access to the full article then it would be very useful to know what reference [4] is. I can only see the preview of the first page.
    – Peter Taylor
    Nov 29 at 8:23
















1














There is a paragragh that I saw in an article and could not really understand. The article is Covering Systems of Congruences, J. Fabrykowski and T. Smotzer, Mathematics Magazine Vol. 78, No. 3 (Jun., 2005), pp. 228-231, DOI: 10.2307/30044163. It starts by discussing problem 9 from the 2002 American Invitational Mathematics Examination (AIME):




PROBLEM. Harold, Tanya, and Ulysses paint a very long fence. Harold starts with the first picket and paints every $h$th picket; Tanya starts with the second picket and paints every $t$th picket; and Ulysses starts with the third picket and paints every $u$th picket. If every picket gets painted exactly once, find all possible triples $(h,t,u)$.




After presenting the solution, the article goes on to say:




One can generalize the AIME problem and ask whether there exists a finite set of congruences, with all moduli distinct and greater than or equal to $2$, that forms a partition of the set of integers. This turns out to be impossible. Relaxing the assumption about partitioning the integers, one can look for finite sets of congruences such that every integer belongs to at least one of them."




Can anyone help explain why the first part is impossible?










share|cite|improve this question
























  • By the way, if you have access to the full article then it would be very useful to know what reference [4] is. I can only see the preview of the first page.
    – Peter Taylor
    Nov 29 at 8:23














1












1








1


1





There is a paragragh that I saw in an article and could not really understand. The article is Covering Systems of Congruences, J. Fabrykowski and T. Smotzer, Mathematics Magazine Vol. 78, No. 3 (Jun., 2005), pp. 228-231, DOI: 10.2307/30044163. It starts by discussing problem 9 from the 2002 American Invitational Mathematics Examination (AIME):




PROBLEM. Harold, Tanya, and Ulysses paint a very long fence. Harold starts with the first picket and paints every $h$th picket; Tanya starts with the second picket and paints every $t$th picket; and Ulysses starts with the third picket and paints every $u$th picket. If every picket gets painted exactly once, find all possible triples $(h,t,u)$.




After presenting the solution, the article goes on to say:




One can generalize the AIME problem and ask whether there exists a finite set of congruences, with all moduli distinct and greater than or equal to $2$, that forms a partition of the set of integers. This turns out to be impossible. Relaxing the assumption about partitioning the integers, one can look for finite sets of congruences such that every integer belongs to at least one of them."




Can anyone help explain why the first part is impossible?










share|cite|improve this question















There is a paragragh that I saw in an article and could not really understand. The article is Covering Systems of Congruences, J. Fabrykowski and T. Smotzer, Mathematics Magazine Vol. 78, No. 3 (Jun., 2005), pp. 228-231, DOI: 10.2307/30044163. It starts by discussing problem 9 from the 2002 American Invitational Mathematics Examination (AIME):




PROBLEM. Harold, Tanya, and Ulysses paint a very long fence. Harold starts with the first picket and paints every $h$th picket; Tanya starts with the second picket and paints every $t$th picket; and Ulysses starts with the third picket and paints every $u$th picket. If every picket gets painted exactly once, find all possible triples $(h,t,u)$.




After presenting the solution, the article goes on to say:




One can generalize the AIME problem and ask whether there exists a finite set of congruences, with all moduli distinct and greater than or equal to $2$, that forms a partition of the set of integers. This turns out to be impossible. Relaxing the assumption about partitioning the integers, one can look for finite sets of congruences such that every integer belongs to at least one of them."




Can anyone help explain why the first part is impossible?







modular-arithmetic set-partition






share|cite|improve this question















share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question








edited Nov 28 at 17:01









Peter Taylor

8,63712240




8,63712240










asked Nov 28 at 3:23









Jingting931015

828




828












  • By the way, if you have access to the full article then it would be very useful to know what reference [4] is. I can only see the preview of the first page.
    – Peter Taylor
    Nov 29 at 8:23


















  • By the way, if you have access to the full article then it would be very useful to know what reference [4] is. I can only see the preview of the first page.
    – Peter Taylor
    Nov 29 at 8:23
















By the way, if you have access to the full article then it would be very useful to know what reference [4] is. I can only see the preview of the first page.
– Peter Taylor
Nov 29 at 8:23




By the way, if you have access to the full article then it would be very useful to know what reference [4] is. I can only see the preview of the first page.
– Peter Taylor
Nov 29 at 8:23










3 Answers
3






active

oldest

votes


















1














This is far from a full answer, but it gives a taste of how strong the constraints are.



Suppose we have $k$ congruences of the form $x equiv a_i pmod {m_i}$ where the $m_i$ are distinct and greater than $1$, and $0 < a_i le m_i$ is the smallest natural number covered by the congruence. Further suppose that we've chosen a minimum set of congruences: i.e. there is no solution with fewer than $k$ congruences.



Consider two distinct congruences $x equiv a_i pmod {m_i}$ and $x equiv a_j pmod {m_j}$. We require $a_i notequiv a_j pmod {gcd(m_i, m_j)}$ to avoid collisions. (This follows from the Chinese remainder theorem, and is necessary and sufficient for non-intersection). Note that this implies that $gcd(m_i, m_j) > 1$, so no two moduli are coprime.



Since a congruence with modulus $m_i$ covers $frac{1}{m_i}$ of the integers, we must have $$sum_i frac{1}{m_i} = 1$$ so we have a partition of unity in Egyptian fractions. Combined with non-intersection, this is necessary and sufficient to partition the natural numbers.



Lemma: no non-trivial proper subset of the congruences is reducible to a single congruence. Suppose that we had a set of congruences $x equiv a_i pmod{m_i}$ which partition $x equiv alpha pmodmu$. Then clearly $m_i equiv 0 pmodmu$ and $a_i equiv alpha pmodmu$, and the congruences $x equiv frac{a_i - alpha}mu pmod {frac{m_i}mu}$ partition the natural numbers. But we started from a proper subset of the congruences, so this contradicts the assumption that $k$ is minimum.



Corollary: there is no $c > 1$ which is a common factor of all of the moduli. (Proof: if there were, one proper subset of the congruences would be reducible to $x equiv 1 pmod c$ and another to $x equiv 2 pmod c$. Since they can't both consist of a single congruence with modulus $c$, one of them is non-trivial, contradicting the lemma).



Corollary: none of the moduli is a prime power, for then that prime must be a common factor of all the moduli.



Corollary: $k ge 19$. (Proof: we have to sum the reciprocals of the first 19 non-prime-powers to exceed $1$. Of course, those 19 numbers don't satisfy the no-pair-coprime constraint, and the sum of their reciprocals isn't exactly unity...).






share|cite|improve this answer





























    -1














    Unfortunately there are finite distinct covering systems. See the system below:



    $0(3), 0(4), 0(5), 1(6), 1(8), 2(10), 11(12), 1(15), 14(20), 5(24), 8(30), 6(40), 58(60), 26(120) $






    share|cite|improve this answer





























      -1














      The answer is yes. There are several.



      This question gives one example: Prove {0 mod 2, 0 mod 3, 1 mod 4, 1 mod 6, 11 mod 12} is a covering system



      $0 mod 2, 0 mod 3, 1mod 4, 1mod 6, 11 mod 12$.



      This paper is all about them https://arxiv.org/pdf/1705.04372.pdf






      share|cite|improve this answer





















        Your Answer





        StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
        return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
        StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
        StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
        });
        });
        }, "mathjax-editing");

        StackExchange.ready(function() {
        var channelOptions = {
        tags: "".split(" "),
        id: "69"
        };
        initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

        StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
        // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
        if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
        StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
        createEditor();
        });
        }
        else {
        createEditor();
        }
        });

        function createEditor() {
        StackExchange.prepareEditor({
        heartbeatType: 'answer',
        autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
        convertImagesToLinks: true,
        noModals: true,
        showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
        reputationToPostImages: 10,
        bindNavPrevention: true,
        postfix: "",
        imageUploader: {
        brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
        contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
        allowUrls: true
        },
        noCode: true, onDemand: true,
        discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
        ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
        });


        }
        });














        draft saved

        draft discarded


















        StackExchange.ready(
        function () {
        StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3016664%2fwhy-does-there-not-exist-a-particular-finite-set-of-congruences-that-forms-a-par%23new-answer', 'question_page');
        }
        );

        Post as a guest















        Required, but never shown

























        3 Answers
        3






        active

        oldest

        votes








        3 Answers
        3






        active

        oldest

        votes









        active

        oldest

        votes






        active

        oldest

        votes









        1














        This is far from a full answer, but it gives a taste of how strong the constraints are.



        Suppose we have $k$ congruences of the form $x equiv a_i pmod {m_i}$ where the $m_i$ are distinct and greater than $1$, and $0 < a_i le m_i$ is the smallest natural number covered by the congruence. Further suppose that we've chosen a minimum set of congruences: i.e. there is no solution with fewer than $k$ congruences.



        Consider two distinct congruences $x equiv a_i pmod {m_i}$ and $x equiv a_j pmod {m_j}$. We require $a_i notequiv a_j pmod {gcd(m_i, m_j)}$ to avoid collisions. (This follows from the Chinese remainder theorem, and is necessary and sufficient for non-intersection). Note that this implies that $gcd(m_i, m_j) > 1$, so no two moduli are coprime.



        Since a congruence with modulus $m_i$ covers $frac{1}{m_i}$ of the integers, we must have $$sum_i frac{1}{m_i} = 1$$ so we have a partition of unity in Egyptian fractions. Combined with non-intersection, this is necessary and sufficient to partition the natural numbers.



        Lemma: no non-trivial proper subset of the congruences is reducible to a single congruence. Suppose that we had a set of congruences $x equiv a_i pmod{m_i}$ which partition $x equiv alpha pmodmu$. Then clearly $m_i equiv 0 pmodmu$ and $a_i equiv alpha pmodmu$, and the congruences $x equiv frac{a_i - alpha}mu pmod {frac{m_i}mu}$ partition the natural numbers. But we started from a proper subset of the congruences, so this contradicts the assumption that $k$ is minimum.



        Corollary: there is no $c > 1$ which is a common factor of all of the moduli. (Proof: if there were, one proper subset of the congruences would be reducible to $x equiv 1 pmod c$ and another to $x equiv 2 pmod c$. Since they can't both consist of a single congruence with modulus $c$, one of them is non-trivial, contradicting the lemma).



        Corollary: none of the moduli is a prime power, for then that prime must be a common factor of all the moduli.



        Corollary: $k ge 19$. (Proof: we have to sum the reciprocals of the first 19 non-prime-powers to exceed $1$. Of course, those 19 numbers don't satisfy the no-pair-coprime constraint, and the sum of their reciprocals isn't exactly unity...).






        share|cite|improve this answer


























          1














          This is far from a full answer, but it gives a taste of how strong the constraints are.



          Suppose we have $k$ congruences of the form $x equiv a_i pmod {m_i}$ where the $m_i$ are distinct and greater than $1$, and $0 < a_i le m_i$ is the smallest natural number covered by the congruence. Further suppose that we've chosen a minimum set of congruences: i.e. there is no solution with fewer than $k$ congruences.



          Consider two distinct congruences $x equiv a_i pmod {m_i}$ and $x equiv a_j pmod {m_j}$. We require $a_i notequiv a_j pmod {gcd(m_i, m_j)}$ to avoid collisions. (This follows from the Chinese remainder theorem, and is necessary and sufficient for non-intersection). Note that this implies that $gcd(m_i, m_j) > 1$, so no two moduli are coprime.



          Since a congruence with modulus $m_i$ covers $frac{1}{m_i}$ of the integers, we must have $$sum_i frac{1}{m_i} = 1$$ so we have a partition of unity in Egyptian fractions. Combined with non-intersection, this is necessary and sufficient to partition the natural numbers.



          Lemma: no non-trivial proper subset of the congruences is reducible to a single congruence. Suppose that we had a set of congruences $x equiv a_i pmod{m_i}$ which partition $x equiv alpha pmodmu$. Then clearly $m_i equiv 0 pmodmu$ and $a_i equiv alpha pmodmu$, and the congruences $x equiv frac{a_i - alpha}mu pmod {frac{m_i}mu}$ partition the natural numbers. But we started from a proper subset of the congruences, so this contradicts the assumption that $k$ is minimum.



          Corollary: there is no $c > 1$ which is a common factor of all of the moduli. (Proof: if there were, one proper subset of the congruences would be reducible to $x equiv 1 pmod c$ and another to $x equiv 2 pmod c$. Since they can't both consist of a single congruence with modulus $c$, one of them is non-trivial, contradicting the lemma).



          Corollary: none of the moduli is a prime power, for then that prime must be a common factor of all the moduli.



          Corollary: $k ge 19$. (Proof: we have to sum the reciprocals of the first 19 non-prime-powers to exceed $1$. Of course, those 19 numbers don't satisfy the no-pair-coprime constraint, and the sum of their reciprocals isn't exactly unity...).






          share|cite|improve this answer
























            1












            1








            1






            This is far from a full answer, but it gives a taste of how strong the constraints are.



            Suppose we have $k$ congruences of the form $x equiv a_i pmod {m_i}$ where the $m_i$ are distinct and greater than $1$, and $0 < a_i le m_i$ is the smallest natural number covered by the congruence. Further suppose that we've chosen a minimum set of congruences: i.e. there is no solution with fewer than $k$ congruences.



            Consider two distinct congruences $x equiv a_i pmod {m_i}$ and $x equiv a_j pmod {m_j}$. We require $a_i notequiv a_j pmod {gcd(m_i, m_j)}$ to avoid collisions. (This follows from the Chinese remainder theorem, and is necessary and sufficient for non-intersection). Note that this implies that $gcd(m_i, m_j) > 1$, so no two moduli are coprime.



            Since a congruence with modulus $m_i$ covers $frac{1}{m_i}$ of the integers, we must have $$sum_i frac{1}{m_i} = 1$$ so we have a partition of unity in Egyptian fractions. Combined with non-intersection, this is necessary and sufficient to partition the natural numbers.



            Lemma: no non-trivial proper subset of the congruences is reducible to a single congruence. Suppose that we had a set of congruences $x equiv a_i pmod{m_i}$ which partition $x equiv alpha pmodmu$. Then clearly $m_i equiv 0 pmodmu$ and $a_i equiv alpha pmodmu$, and the congruences $x equiv frac{a_i - alpha}mu pmod {frac{m_i}mu}$ partition the natural numbers. But we started from a proper subset of the congruences, so this contradicts the assumption that $k$ is minimum.



            Corollary: there is no $c > 1$ which is a common factor of all of the moduli. (Proof: if there were, one proper subset of the congruences would be reducible to $x equiv 1 pmod c$ and another to $x equiv 2 pmod c$. Since they can't both consist of a single congruence with modulus $c$, one of them is non-trivial, contradicting the lemma).



            Corollary: none of the moduli is a prime power, for then that prime must be a common factor of all the moduli.



            Corollary: $k ge 19$. (Proof: we have to sum the reciprocals of the first 19 non-prime-powers to exceed $1$. Of course, those 19 numbers don't satisfy the no-pair-coprime constraint, and the sum of their reciprocals isn't exactly unity...).






            share|cite|improve this answer












            This is far from a full answer, but it gives a taste of how strong the constraints are.



            Suppose we have $k$ congruences of the form $x equiv a_i pmod {m_i}$ where the $m_i$ are distinct and greater than $1$, and $0 < a_i le m_i$ is the smallest natural number covered by the congruence. Further suppose that we've chosen a minimum set of congruences: i.e. there is no solution with fewer than $k$ congruences.



            Consider two distinct congruences $x equiv a_i pmod {m_i}$ and $x equiv a_j pmod {m_j}$. We require $a_i notequiv a_j pmod {gcd(m_i, m_j)}$ to avoid collisions. (This follows from the Chinese remainder theorem, and is necessary and sufficient for non-intersection). Note that this implies that $gcd(m_i, m_j) > 1$, so no two moduli are coprime.



            Since a congruence with modulus $m_i$ covers $frac{1}{m_i}$ of the integers, we must have $$sum_i frac{1}{m_i} = 1$$ so we have a partition of unity in Egyptian fractions. Combined with non-intersection, this is necessary and sufficient to partition the natural numbers.



            Lemma: no non-trivial proper subset of the congruences is reducible to a single congruence. Suppose that we had a set of congruences $x equiv a_i pmod{m_i}$ which partition $x equiv alpha pmodmu$. Then clearly $m_i equiv 0 pmodmu$ and $a_i equiv alpha pmodmu$, and the congruences $x equiv frac{a_i - alpha}mu pmod {frac{m_i}mu}$ partition the natural numbers. But we started from a proper subset of the congruences, so this contradicts the assumption that $k$ is minimum.



            Corollary: there is no $c > 1$ which is a common factor of all of the moduli. (Proof: if there were, one proper subset of the congruences would be reducible to $x equiv 1 pmod c$ and another to $x equiv 2 pmod c$. Since they can't both consist of a single congruence with modulus $c$, one of them is non-trivial, contradicting the lemma).



            Corollary: none of the moduli is a prime power, for then that prime must be a common factor of all the moduli.



            Corollary: $k ge 19$. (Proof: we have to sum the reciprocals of the first 19 non-prime-powers to exceed $1$. Of course, those 19 numbers don't satisfy the no-pair-coprime constraint, and the sum of their reciprocals isn't exactly unity...).







            share|cite|improve this answer












            share|cite|improve this answer



            share|cite|improve this answer










            answered Nov 28 at 22:46









            Peter Taylor

            8,63712240




            8,63712240























                -1














                Unfortunately there are finite distinct covering systems. See the system below:



                $0(3), 0(4), 0(5), 1(6), 1(8), 2(10), 11(12), 1(15), 14(20), 5(24), 8(30), 6(40), 58(60), 26(120) $






                share|cite|improve this answer


























                  -1














                  Unfortunately there are finite distinct covering systems. See the system below:



                  $0(3), 0(4), 0(5), 1(6), 1(8), 2(10), 11(12), 1(15), 14(20), 5(24), 8(30), 6(40), 58(60), 26(120) $






                  share|cite|improve this answer
























                    -1












                    -1








                    -1






                    Unfortunately there are finite distinct covering systems. See the system below:



                    $0(3), 0(4), 0(5), 1(6), 1(8), 2(10), 11(12), 1(15), 14(20), 5(24), 8(30), 6(40), 58(60), 26(120) $






                    share|cite|improve this answer












                    Unfortunately there are finite distinct covering systems. See the system below:



                    $0(3), 0(4), 0(5), 1(6), 1(8), 2(10), 11(12), 1(15), 14(20), 5(24), 8(30), 6(40), 58(60), 26(120) $







                    share|cite|improve this answer












                    share|cite|improve this answer



                    share|cite|improve this answer










                    answered Nov 28 at 3:31









                    Valborg

                    792




                    792























                        -1














                        The answer is yes. There are several.



                        This question gives one example: Prove {0 mod 2, 0 mod 3, 1 mod 4, 1 mod 6, 11 mod 12} is a covering system



                        $0 mod 2, 0 mod 3, 1mod 4, 1mod 6, 11 mod 12$.



                        This paper is all about them https://arxiv.org/pdf/1705.04372.pdf






                        share|cite|improve this answer


























                          -1














                          The answer is yes. There are several.



                          This question gives one example: Prove {0 mod 2, 0 mod 3, 1 mod 4, 1 mod 6, 11 mod 12} is a covering system



                          $0 mod 2, 0 mod 3, 1mod 4, 1mod 6, 11 mod 12$.



                          This paper is all about them https://arxiv.org/pdf/1705.04372.pdf






                          share|cite|improve this answer
























                            -1












                            -1








                            -1






                            The answer is yes. There are several.



                            This question gives one example: Prove {0 mod 2, 0 mod 3, 1 mod 4, 1 mod 6, 11 mod 12} is a covering system



                            $0 mod 2, 0 mod 3, 1mod 4, 1mod 6, 11 mod 12$.



                            This paper is all about them https://arxiv.org/pdf/1705.04372.pdf






                            share|cite|improve this answer












                            The answer is yes. There are several.



                            This question gives one example: Prove {0 mod 2, 0 mod 3, 1 mod 4, 1 mod 6, 11 mod 12} is a covering system



                            $0 mod 2, 0 mod 3, 1mod 4, 1mod 6, 11 mod 12$.



                            This paper is all about them https://arxiv.org/pdf/1705.04372.pdf







                            share|cite|improve this answer












                            share|cite|improve this answer



                            share|cite|improve this answer










                            answered Nov 28 at 3:55









                            fleablood

                            68k22684




                            68k22684






























                                draft saved

                                draft discarded




















































                                Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


                                • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

                                But avoid



                                • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

                                • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


                                Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


                                To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.





                                Some of your past answers have not been well-received, and you're in danger of being blocked from answering.


                                Please pay close attention to the following guidance:


                                • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

                                But avoid



                                • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

                                • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


                                To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




                                draft saved


                                draft discarded














                                StackExchange.ready(
                                function () {
                                StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3016664%2fwhy-does-there-not-exist-a-particular-finite-set-of-congruences-that-forms-a-par%23new-answer', 'question_page');
                                }
                                );

                                Post as a guest















                                Required, but never shown





















































                                Required, but never shown














                                Required, but never shown












                                Required, but never shown







                                Required, but never shown

































                                Required, but never shown














                                Required, but never shown












                                Required, but never shown







                                Required, but never shown







                                Popular posts from this blog

                                To store a contact into the json file from server.js file using a class in NodeJS

                                Redirect URL with Chrome Remote Debugging Android Devices

                                Dieringhausen