An alternative, more formal proof of a path lifting criterion in tom Dieck's Algebraic Topology












0












$begingroup$


This is a theorem from Tammo tom Dieck's Algebraic Topology:





While it has a direct proof, the author gives a more formal proof in the problems:





By pullback I suppose he means a diagram
$require{AMScd}$
begin{CD}
Ztimes_BE @>k>> E\
@V V q V @V V p V\
Z @>>f> B
end{CD}



However, I don't see how the existence of a lifting $Phi:Zto E$ is equivalent to the existence of a section $s:Zto Ztimes_BE$. (Even if you have a section $s$ and define $Phi:=ks$, it need not satisfy $Phi(z)=x$.) Also, he uses $E_b$ to denote that fibre, which suggests that it should be a subset of $E$. But in this pullback $q$ the fibre lives in $Ztimes_B E$.



I think I may have misunderstood the problem. Could you please tell me what he means by this? Thanks in advance!










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Use the universal property for pullbacks, that the projections induce an bijection between the set of maps $a:Krightarrow Z$ and $b:Krightarrow E$ satisfying $fcirc a=pcirc b$ and the set of maps $Krightarrow Ztimes_BE$. Take $K=Z$, and $a=id_Z$ and $b=Phi$ to get a section $s:Zrightarrow Ztimes_BE$. On the other hand, if $s$ is section of $q$, then $kcirc s$ is a lifting of $f$, since $pcirc kcirc s=fcirc qcirc s=fcirc id_Z=f$.
    $endgroup$
    – Tyrone
    Dec 8 '18 at 15:34












  • $begingroup$
    I belive tom Dieck says a few words regarding the situation at the top of pg. 9 (at least in the edition I have). I suppose you could consider this indicative ofa positive answer to your last question: the abstract machinery developed is eventually put to good use. (Although I wouldn't go as far as to suggest that it is all used in this book).
    $endgroup$
    – Tyrone
    Dec 8 '18 at 15:38












  • $begingroup$
    @Tyrone Why not an official answer?
    $endgroup$
    – Paul Frost
    Dec 8 '18 at 16:19










  • $begingroup$
    If @colescu feels that what I have written addresses his question I will be happy to shape it into a complete answer.
    $endgroup$
    – Tyrone
    Dec 8 '18 at 23:19










  • $begingroup$
    @Tyrone I remember seeing you on my other question. Thank you! Regarding this question: I understand your comment. So we need to further require that $s$ has $ks(z)=x$? But I still don't see the argument... Is the fibre $E_bsubseteq Ztimes_B E$? I don't see how $pi_1(B,b)$ acts on $E_b$. I only know the monodromy action of $pi_1(B,b)$ on fibres in $E$. Lastly and most importantly, even if I know the action, why is the existence of a section equivalent to the existence of a fixed point? (I tried to guess the action by this, but failed...)
    $endgroup$
    – Colescu
    Dec 9 '18 at 0:45
















0












$begingroup$


This is a theorem from Tammo tom Dieck's Algebraic Topology:





While it has a direct proof, the author gives a more formal proof in the problems:





By pullback I suppose he means a diagram
$require{AMScd}$
begin{CD}
Ztimes_BE @>k>> E\
@V V q V @V V p V\
Z @>>f> B
end{CD}



However, I don't see how the existence of a lifting $Phi:Zto E$ is equivalent to the existence of a section $s:Zto Ztimes_BE$. (Even if you have a section $s$ and define $Phi:=ks$, it need not satisfy $Phi(z)=x$.) Also, he uses $E_b$ to denote that fibre, which suggests that it should be a subset of $E$. But in this pullback $q$ the fibre lives in $Ztimes_B E$.



I think I may have misunderstood the problem. Could you please tell me what he means by this? Thanks in advance!










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Use the universal property for pullbacks, that the projections induce an bijection between the set of maps $a:Krightarrow Z$ and $b:Krightarrow E$ satisfying $fcirc a=pcirc b$ and the set of maps $Krightarrow Ztimes_BE$. Take $K=Z$, and $a=id_Z$ and $b=Phi$ to get a section $s:Zrightarrow Ztimes_BE$. On the other hand, if $s$ is section of $q$, then $kcirc s$ is a lifting of $f$, since $pcirc kcirc s=fcirc qcirc s=fcirc id_Z=f$.
    $endgroup$
    – Tyrone
    Dec 8 '18 at 15:34












  • $begingroup$
    I belive tom Dieck says a few words regarding the situation at the top of pg. 9 (at least in the edition I have). I suppose you could consider this indicative ofa positive answer to your last question: the abstract machinery developed is eventually put to good use. (Although I wouldn't go as far as to suggest that it is all used in this book).
    $endgroup$
    – Tyrone
    Dec 8 '18 at 15:38












  • $begingroup$
    @Tyrone Why not an official answer?
    $endgroup$
    – Paul Frost
    Dec 8 '18 at 16:19










  • $begingroup$
    If @colescu feels that what I have written addresses his question I will be happy to shape it into a complete answer.
    $endgroup$
    – Tyrone
    Dec 8 '18 at 23:19










  • $begingroup$
    @Tyrone I remember seeing you on my other question. Thank you! Regarding this question: I understand your comment. So we need to further require that $s$ has $ks(z)=x$? But I still don't see the argument... Is the fibre $E_bsubseteq Ztimes_B E$? I don't see how $pi_1(B,b)$ acts on $E_b$. I only know the monodromy action of $pi_1(B,b)$ on fibres in $E$. Lastly and most importantly, even if I know the action, why is the existence of a section equivalent to the existence of a fixed point? (I tried to guess the action by this, but failed...)
    $endgroup$
    – Colescu
    Dec 9 '18 at 0:45














0












0








0


2



$begingroup$


This is a theorem from Tammo tom Dieck's Algebraic Topology:





While it has a direct proof, the author gives a more formal proof in the problems:





By pullback I suppose he means a diagram
$require{AMScd}$
begin{CD}
Ztimes_BE @>k>> E\
@V V q V @V V p V\
Z @>>f> B
end{CD}



However, I don't see how the existence of a lifting $Phi:Zto E$ is equivalent to the existence of a section $s:Zto Ztimes_BE$. (Even if you have a section $s$ and define $Phi:=ks$, it need not satisfy $Phi(z)=x$.) Also, he uses $E_b$ to denote that fibre, which suggests that it should be a subset of $E$. But in this pullback $q$ the fibre lives in $Ztimes_B E$.



I think I may have misunderstood the problem. Could you please tell me what he means by this? Thanks in advance!










share|cite|improve this question









$endgroup$




This is a theorem from Tammo tom Dieck's Algebraic Topology:





While it has a direct proof, the author gives a more formal proof in the problems:





By pullback I suppose he means a diagram
$require{AMScd}$
begin{CD}
Ztimes_BE @>k>> E\
@V V q V @V V p V\
Z @>>f> B
end{CD}



However, I don't see how the existence of a lifting $Phi:Zto E$ is equivalent to the existence of a section $s:Zto Ztimes_BE$. (Even if you have a section $s$ and define $Phi:=ks$, it need not satisfy $Phi(z)=x$.) Also, he uses $E_b$ to denote that fibre, which suggests that it should be a subset of $E$. But in this pullback $q$ the fibre lives in $Ztimes_B E$.



I think I may have misunderstood the problem. Could you please tell me what he means by this? Thanks in advance!







algebraic-topology homotopy-theory covering-spaces






share|cite|improve this question













share|cite|improve this question











share|cite|improve this question




share|cite|improve this question










asked Dec 8 '18 at 13:11









ColescuColescu

3,0951736




3,0951736








  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Use the universal property for pullbacks, that the projections induce an bijection between the set of maps $a:Krightarrow Z$ and $b:Krightarrow E$ satisfying $fcirc a=pcirc b$ and the set of maps $Krightarrow Ztimes_BE$. Take $K=Z$, and $a=id_Z$ and $b=Phi$ to get a section $s:Zrightarrow Ztimes_BE$. On the other hand, if $s$ is section of $q$, then $kcirc s$ is a lifting of $f$, since $pcirc kcirc s=fcirc qcirc s=fcirc id_Z=f$.
    $endgroup$
    – Tyrone
    Dec 8 '18 at 15:34












  • $begingroup$
    I belive tom Dieck says a few words regarding the situation at the top of pg. 9 (at least in the edition I have). I suppose you could consider this indicative ofa positive answer to your last question: the abstract machinery developed is eventually put to good use. (Although I wouldn't go as far as to suggest that it is all used in this book).
    $endgroup$
    – Tyrone
    Dec 8 '18 at 15:38












  • $begingroup$
    @Tyrone Why not an official answer?
    $endgroup$
    – Paul Frost
    Dec 8 '18 at 16:19










  • $begingroup$
    If @colescu feels that what I have written addresses his question I will be happy to shape it into a complete answer.
    $endgroup$
    – Tyrone
    Dec 8 '18 at 23:19










  • $begingroup$
    @Tyrone I remember seeing you on my other question. Thank you! Regarding this question: I understand your comment. So we need to further require that $s$ has $ks(z)=x$? But I still don't see the argument... Is the fibre $E_bsubseteq Ztimes_B E$? I don't see how $pi_1(B,b)$ acts on $E_b$. I only know the monodromy action of $pi_1(B,b)$ on fibres in $E$. Lastly and most importantly, even if I know the action, why is the existence of a section equivalent to the existence of a fixed point? (I tried to guess the action by this, but failed...)
    $endgroup$
    – Colescu
    Dec 9 '18 at 0:45














  • 1




    $begingroup$
    Use the universal property for pullbacks, that the projections induce an bijection between the set of maps $a:Krightarrow Z$ and $b:Krightarrow E$ satisfying $fcirc a=pcirc b$ and the set of maps $Krightarrow Ztimes_BE$. Take $K=Z$, and $a=id_Z$ and $b=Phi$ to get a section $s:Zrightarrow Ztimes_BE$. On the other hand, if $s$ is section of $q$, then $kcirc s$ is a lifting of $f$, since $pcirc kcirc s=fcirc qcirc s=fcirc id_Z=f$.
    $endgroup$
    – Tyrone
    Dec 8 '18 at 15:34












  • $begingroup$
    I belive tom Dieck says a few words regarding the situation at the top of pg. 9 (at least in the edition I have). I suppose you could consider this indicative ofa positive answer to your last question: the abstract machinery developed is eventually put to good use. (Although I wouldn't go as far as to suggest that it is all used in this book).
    $endgroup$
    – Tyrone
    Dec 8 '18 at 15:38












  • $begingroup$
    @Tyrone Why not an official answer?
    $endgroup$
    – Paul Frost
    Dec 8 '18 at 16:19










  • $begingroup$
    If @colescu feels that what I have written addresses his question I will be happy to shape it into a complete answer.
    $endgroup$
    – Tyrone
    Dec 8 '18 at 23:19










  • $begingroup$
    @Tyrone I remember seeing you on my other question. Thank you! Regarding this question: I understand your comment. So we need to further require that $s$ has $ks(z)=x$? But I still don't see the argument... Is the fibre $E_bsubseteq Ztimes_B E$? I don't see how $pi_1(B,b)$ acts on $E_b$. I only know the monodromy action of $pi_1(B,b)$ on fibres in $E$. Lastly and most importantly, even if I know the action, why is the existence of a section equivalent to the existence of a fixed point? (I tried to guess the action by this, but failed...)
    $endgroup$
    – Colescu
    Dec 9 '18 at 0:45








1




1




$begingroup$
Use the universal property for pullbacks, that the projections induce an bijection between the set of maps $a:Krightarrow Z$ and $b:Krightarrow E$ satisfying $fcirc a=pcirc b$ and the set of maps $Krightarrow Ztimes_BE$. Take $K=Z$, and $a=id_Z$ and $b=Phi$ to get a section $s:Zrightarrow Ztimes_BE$. On the other hand, if $s$ is section of $q$, then $kcirc s$ is a lifting of $f$, since $pcirc kcirc s=fcirc qcirc s=fcirc id_Z=f$.
$endgroup$
– Tyrone
Dec 8 '18 at 15:34






$begingroup$
Use the universal property for pullbacks, that the projections induce an bijection between the set of maps $a:Krightarrow Z$ and $b:Krightarrow E$ satisfying $fcirc a=pcirc b$ and the set of maps $Krightarrow Ztimes_BE$. Take $K=Z$, and $a=id_Z$ and $b=Phi$ to get a section $s:Zrightarrow Ztimes_BE$. On the other hand, if $s$ is section of $q$, then $kcirc s$ is a lifting of $f$, since $pcirc kcirc s=fcirc qcirc s=fcirc id_Z=f$.
$endgroup$
– Tyrone
Dec 8 '18 at 15:34














$begingroup$
I belive tom Dieck says a few words regarding the situation at the top of pg. 9 (at least in the edition I have). I suppose you could consider this indicative ofa positive answer to your last question: the abstract machinery developed is eventually put to good use. (Although I wouldn't go as far as to suggest that it is all used in this book).
$endgroup$
– Tyrone
Dec 8 '18 at 15:38






$begingroup$
I belive tom Dieck says a few words regarding the situation at the top of pg. 9 (at least in the edition I have). I suppose you could consider this indicative ofa positive answer to your last question: the abstract machinery developed is eventually put to good use. (Although I wouldn't go as far as to suggest that it is all used in this book).
$endgroup$
– Tyrone
Dec 8 '18 at 15:38














$begingroup$
@Tyrone Why not an official answer?
$endgroup$
– Paul Frost
Dec 8 '18 at 16:19




$begingroup$
@Tyrone Why not an official answer?
$endgroup$
– Paul Frost
Dec 8 '18 at 16:19












$begingroup$
If @colescu feels that what I have written addresses his question I will be happy to shape it into a complete answer.
$endgroup$
– Tyrone
Dec 8 '18 at 23:19




$begingroup$
If @colescu feels that what I have written addresses his question I will be happy to shape it into a complete answer.
$endgroup$
– Tyrone
Dec 8 '18 at 23:19












$begingroup$
@Tyrone I remember seeing you on my other question. Thank you! Regarding this question: I understand your comment. So we need to further require that $s$ has $ks(z)=x$? But I still don't see the argument... Is the fibre $E_bsubseteq Ztimes_B E$? I don't see how $pi_1(B,b)$ acts on $E_b$. I only know the monodromy action of $pi_1(B,b)$ on fibres in $E$. Lastly and most importantly, even if I know the action, why is the existence of a section equivalent to the existence of a fixed point? (I tried to guess the action by this, but failed...)
$endgroup$
– Colescu
Dec 9 '18 at 0:45




$begingroup$
@Tyrone I remember seeing you on my other question. Thank you! Regarding this question: I understand your comment. So we need to further require that $s$ has $ks(z)=x$? But I still don't see the argument... Is the fibre $E_bsubseteq Ztimes_B E$? I don't see how $pi_1(B,b)$ acts on $E_b$. I only know the monodromy action of $pi_1(B,b)$ on fibres in $E$. Lastly and most importantly, even if I know the action, why is the existence of a section equivalent to the existence of a fixed point? (I tried to guess the action by this, but failed...)
$endgroup$
– Colescu
Dec 9 '18 at 0:45










2 Answers
2






active

oldest

votes


















3












$begingroup$

Form the pullback $f^*E=Ztimes_BE$. This space sits in a strictly commutative diagram
$require{AMScd}$
begin{CD}
f^*E=Ztimes_BE@>k>> E\
@VVq V @VV p V\
Z @>f>> B
end{CD}

and has the universal property that for any space $A$ the projections $q,k$ induce a 1-1 correspondence



$${text{maps}: Arightarrow Ztimes_BE}leftrightarrows{text{pairs};(a:Arightarrow Z, b:Arightarrow E)mid fcirc a=pcirc b}.$$



Explicitly we send $F:Arightarrow Ztimes_BE$ to the pair $(qcirc F,kcirc F)$. The pullback is characterised by this universal property and so is unique up to homeomorphism. If you like you can take the standard model



$$Ztimes_BE={(z,e)in Ztimes Emid f(z)=p(e)}subseteq Ztimes E,$$



with the maps $q,k$ induced by projection onto each factor. In this way we make explicit the inverse to previous function: if $a:Arightarrow Z$, $b:Arightarrow E$ satisfy $fcirc a=pcirc b$ then we define $atimes_Bb:Arightarrow Ztimes_BE$ by $(atimes_Bb)(x)=(a(x),b(x))$, $xin A$. One check that this is well-defined and continuous.



In this way we get the correspondence between liftings of $f$ and sections of $q:Ztimes_BErightarrow Z$. If $Phi:Zrightarrow E$ lifts $f$ through $p$ then it satisfies $pcirc Phi=f$, and so the pair $(id_Z,Phi)$, which lives on the right-hand side of the previous correspondence, induces a map $s_Phi:Zrightarrow Ztimes_BE$ which will satisfy



$$qcirc s_Phi=id_Z,qquad kcirc s_Phi=Phi.$$



In particular the first of these conditions shows that $s_Phi$ is a section of $q$.



On the other hand, if $s:Zrightarrow Ztimes_BE$ is a section of $q$ then $Phi_s=kcirc s:Zrightarrow E$ lifts $f$. To wit,



$$pcirc Phi_s=pcirc (kcirc s)=(pcirc k)circ s=(fcirc q)circ s=fcirc (qcirc s)=fcirc id_z=f.$$



As for the condition $Phi_s(z)=x$ we observe that the fibre of $q$ over $a$ is homeomorphic to the fibre of $p$ of $f(z)$, the maps in the defining commutative square inducing the isomorphism. In fact using the explicit model gives us



$$(Ztimes_BE)_z={(z,e)mid f(z)=p(e)}cong {z}times E_{f(z)}.$$



Thus the requirement $Phi_s(z)=x$ is equivalent to the condition $s(z)=(z,x)$. From here one proceeds directly as in the given proof of (3.5.2) to get the result.



However, I think you are after a more extended discussion, especially relating to the exercise [3.5.1]. For this, I belive that tom Dieck is interested in the case that both $B$ and $Z$ are path connected, locally path connected and semi-locally simply connected, so I will assume these additional hypotheses.



Thus by (3.3.2) Classification I, and (3.4.1), the category of coverings $Cov_Z$ of $Z$ is equivalent to the category of $pi_zmbox-Set$ of (left) $pi_z=pi_1(Z,z)$-sets, where $zin Z$ is a chosen element. Above we have produced a pullback covering $q:f^*E=Ztimes_BErightarrow Z$ over $Z$, and this therefore corresponds to some $pi_z$-set which we'll denote $f^*mathcal{E}$. In fact we can see explicitly what this set is by what I have written above. The covering $p:Erightarrow B$ corresponds in $pi_{f(z)}$-set to the $pi_1(B,f(z))$-set given by the fibre $E_{f(z)}$. Therefore its pullback $f^*mathcal{E}$ should correspond to the $pi_z$-set given by the fibre



$$(f^*E)_zcong {z}times E_{f(z)},$$



and $pi_1(Z,z)$ should act on this set by the pullback action, that is,



$$alphacdot (z,e)=(z,(f_*alpha)cdot e),qquad (z,e)in f^*E,alphainpi_1(Z,z).$$



Now we can view a section $s:Zrightarrow f^*E$ of the pullback as a morphism of covering spaces
$require{AMScd}$
begin{CD}
Z@>s>> f^*E\
@VV= V @VV q V\
Z @>=>> Z,
end{CD}

and this corresponds to a morphism $mathfrak{s}:{z}rightarrow f^*mathcal{E}$ in $pi_z$-Set . Here I have used that the trivial covering $id_Z:Zrightarrow Z$ with one-point fibres corresponds to the trivial one-point $pi_z$-set ${z}$. Such a $pi_1$-equivariant morphism $mathfrak{s}$ must take the $pi_z$-fixed element $z$ into an element of $f^*mathcal{E}$ which is fixed under the pullback $pi_z$-action. This is exactly the statement that $E_{f(z)}$ has a fixed point under the $pi_1(Z,z)$-action.



On the other hand, if $kin f^*mathcal{E}$ is fixed by the pullback $pi_z$-action, then $mathfrak{s}:{z}rightarrow f^*mathcal{E}$, $ymapsto k$, is well-defined in $pi_z$-Set and so gives rise to a section $s:Zrightarrow f^*E$ in $Cov_Z$ since these categores are equivalent.



Finally, according to (3.2.8) the isotropy subgroup of $xin E_{f(z)}$ is exactly the image of $p_*:pi_1(E,x)rightarrow pi_1(B,f(z))$, so putting everything together, $(f^*E)_zcong{z}times E_{f(z)}$ will have a fixed point under the $pi_1(Z,z)$ action whenever $f_*(pi_1(Z,z))subseteq p_*pi_1(E,x)$. Hence the conditions are sufficente to choose a section $zmapsto (z,e)$ of $f^*E$, which by the previous is equivalent to a lifting $Phi:Zrightarrow E$, satisfying $Phi(z)=x$.






share|cite|improve this answer









$endgroup$













  • $begingroup$
    Wow, so the section actually comes from the equvalence of categories! Now I see what he's talking about. Thanks for the inspiring answer! (BTW, I'd consider this proof somewhat flawed since the direct proof does not assume $Z$ is semi-locally simply connected.)
    $endgroup$
    – Colescu
    Dec 10 '18 at 0:45



















1












$begingroup$

I just found a simpler proof that works without the hypothesis that $B$ is semi-locally simply connected (and therefore without using sophisticated results on the classification of covering spaces for such spaces). Moreover, I think it is closer to what the author had in mind.



First, for any covering $p:Eto B$, we have the transport functor $T_p:Pi(B)tomathsf{SET}$, where $T_p(b)=p^{-1}(b)$ for $bin B$, and for $v:Ito B$ the map $T_p(v):p^{-1}(v(0))to p^{-1}(v(1))$ is defined thus: given $ein p^{-1}(v(0))$ lift $v$ to $V:Ito E$ (i.e., $pV=v$) with initial condition $V(0)=e$ and set $[T_p(v)](e):=V(1)$. (This is introduced on page 67 of tom Dieck's book.)



The proof begins. We use the pushout
begin{CD}
Y @>k>> E\
@V V q V @V V p V\
Z @>>f> B
end{CD}

where $Y:={,(z,x)in Ztimes E:f(z)=p(x),}$ and $q,k$ are projections onto the coordinates. Then $q$ is also a covering. This induces transport functors $T_p:Pi(B)tomathsf{SET}$, $T_q:Pi(Z)tomathsf{SET}.$ Now observe that $T_q(z)={z}times p^{-1}(f(z))cong T_p(f(z))$ and this is a natural equivalence $eta:T_qsimeq T_pcircPi(f)$. (This is actually Problem 3.3.2 in disguise.) In particular we have a commutative diagram
begin{CD}
q^{-1}(z) @>eta_z>> p^{-1}(f(z))\
@V V T_q(v) V @V V T_p(fv) V\
q^{-1}(z) @>>eta_z> p^{-1}(f(z))
end{CD}

where $vinpi_1(Z,z)$. Thus $pi_1(Z,z)$ acts on $p^{-1}(f(z))$ if we identify $q^{-1}(z)$ and $p^{-1}(f(z))$ via $eta$.



The condition $f_*(pi_1(Z,z))subset p_*(pi_1(E,x))$ says $pi_1(Z,z)$ fixes $x$. So $q_*:pi_1(Y,(z,x))topi_1(Z,z)$ is an isomorphism. (tom Dieck, page 69, Proposition 3.2.8) If we take the component $Y_0$ of $Y$ containing $(z,x)$, then $q_0:=qmid_{Y_0}:Y_0to Z$ is a covering (tom Dieck, page 64, Remark 3.1.6; local path connectedness is used here) with fiber consisting of a single point, i.e., $q_0$ is a homeomorphism. (This gives the section mentioned in the exercise.) Finally, $kq_0^{-1}$ gives the desired lifting.






share|cite|improve this answer











$endgroup$













    Your Answer





    StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
    return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
    StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
    StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
    });
    });
    }, "mathjax-editing");

    StackExchange.ready(function() {
    var channelOptions = {
    tags: "".split(" "),
    id: "69"
    };
    initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);

    StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
    // Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
    if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
    StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
    createEditor();
    });
    }
    else {
    createEditor();
    }
    });

    function createEditor() {
    StackExchange.prepareEditor({
    heartbeatType: 'answer',
    autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
    convertImagesToLinks: true,
    noModals: true,
    showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
    reputationToPostImages: 10,
    bindNavPrevention: true,
    postfix: "",
    imageUploader: {
    brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
    contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
    allowUrls: true
    },
    noCode: true, onDemand: true,
    discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
    ,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
    });


    }
    });














    draft saved

    draft discarded


















    StackExchange.ready(
    function () {
    StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3031092%2fan-alternative-more-formal-proof-of-a-path-lifting-criterion-in-tom-diecks-alg%23new-answer', 'question_page');
    }
    );

    Post as a guest















    Required, but never shown

























    2 Answers
    2






    active

    oldest

    votes








    2 Answers
    2






    active

    oldest

    votes









    active

    oldest

    votes






    active

    oldest

    votes









    3












    $begingroup$

    Form the pullback $f^*E=Ztimes_BE$. This space sits in a strictly commutative diagram
    $require{AMScd}$
    begin{CD}
    f^*E=Ztimes_BE@>k>> E\
    @VVq V @VV p V\
    Z @>f>> B
    end{CD}

    and has the universal property that for any space $A$ the projections $q,k$ induce a 1-1 correspondence



    $${text{maps}: Arightarrow Ztimes_BE}leftrightarrows{text{pairs};(a:Arightarrow Z, b:Arightarrow E)mid fcirc a=pcirc b}.$$



    Explicitly we send $F:Arightarrow Ztimes_BE$ to the pair $(qcirc F,kcirc F)$. The pullback is characterised by this universal property and so is unique up to homeomorphism. If you like you can take the standard model



    $$Ztimes_BE={(z,e)in Ztimes Emid f(z)=p(e)}subseteq Ztimes E,$$



    with the maps $q,k$ induced by projection onto each factor. In this way we make explicit the inverse to previous function: if $a:Arightarrow Z$, $b:Arightarrow E$ satisfy $fcirc a=pcirc b$ then we define $atimes_Bb:Arightarrow Ztimes_BE$ by $(atimes_Bb)(x)=(a(x),b(x))$, $xin A$. One check that this is well-defined and continuous.



    In this way we get the correspondence between liftings of $f$ and sections of $q:Ztimes_BErightarrow Z$. If $Phi:Zrightarrow E$ lifts $f$ through $p$ then it satisfies $pcirc Phi=f$, and so the pair $(id_Z,Phi)$, which lives on the right-hand side of the previous correspondence, induces a map $s_Phi:Zrightarrow Ztimes_BE$ which will satisfy



    $$qcirc s_Phi=id_Z,qquad kcirc s_Phi=Phi.$$



    In particular the first of these conditions shows that $s_Phi$ is a section of $q$.



    On the other hand, if $s:Zrightarrow Ztimes_BE$ is a section of $q$ then $Phi_s=kcirc s:Zrightarrow E$ lifts $f$. To wit,



    $$pcirc Phi_s=pcirc (kcirc s)=(pcirc k)circ s=(fcirc q)circ s=fcirc (qcirc s)=fcirc id_z=f.$$



    As for the condition $Phi_s(z)=x$ we observe that the fibre of $q$ over $a$ is homeomorphic to the fibre of $p$ of $f(z)$, the maps in the defining commutative square inducing the isomorphism. In fact using the explicit model gives us



    $$(Ztimes_BE)_z={(z,e)mid f(z)=p(e)}cong {z}times E_{f(z)}.$$



    Thus the requirement $Phi_s(z)=x$ is equivalent to the condition $s(z)=(z,x)$. From here one proceeds directly as in the given proof of (3.5.2) to get the result.



    However, I think you are after a more extended discussion, especially relating to the exercise [3.5.1]. For this, I belive that tom Dieck is interested in the case that both $B$ and $Z$ are path connected, locally path connected and semi-locally simply connected, so I will assume these additional hypotheses.



    Thus by (3.3.2) Classification I, and (3.4.1), the category of coverings $Cov_Z$ of $Z$ is equivalent to the category of $pi_zmbox-Set$ of (left) $pi_z=pi_1(Z,z)$-sets, where $zin Z$ is a chosen element. Above we have produced a pullback covering $q:f^*E=Ztimes_BErightarrow Z$ over $Z$, and this therefore corresponds to some $pi_z$-set which we'll denote $f^*mathcal{E}$. In fact we can see explicitly what this set is by what I have written above. The covering $p:Erightarrow B$ corresponds in $pi_{f(z)}$-set to the $pi_1(B,f(z))$-set given by the fibre $E_{f(z)}$. Therefore its pullback $f^*mathcal{E}$ should correspond to the $pi_z$-set given by the fibre



    $$(f^*E)_zcong {z}times E_{f(z)},$$



    and $pi_1(Z,z)$ should act on this set by the pullback action, that is,



    $$alphacdot (z,e)=(z,(f_*alpha)cdot e),qquad (z,e)in f^*E,alphainpi_1(Z,z).$$



    Now we can view a section $s:Zrightarrow f^*E$ of the pullback as a morphism of covering spaces
    $require{AMScd}$
    begin{CD}
    Z@>s>> f^*E\
    @VV= V @VV q V\
    Z @>=>> Z,
    end{CD}

    and this corresponds to a morphism $mathfrak{s}:{z}rightarrow f^*mathcal{E}$ in $pi_z$-Set . Here I have used that the trivial covering $id_Z:Zrightarrow Z$ with one-point fibres corresponds to the trivial one-point $pi_z$-set ${z}$. Such a $pi_1$-equivariant morphism $mathfrak{s}$ must take the $pi_z$-fixed element $z$ into an element of $f^*mathcal{E}$ which is fixed under the pullback $pi_z$-action. This is exactly the statement that $E_{f(z)}$ has a fixed point under the $pi_1(Z,z)$-action.



    On the other hand, if $kin f^*mathcal{E}$ is fixed by the pullback $pi_z$-action, then $mathfrak{s}:{z}rightarrow f^*mathcal{E}$, $ymapsto k$, is well-defined in $pi_z$-Set and so gives rise to a section $s:Zrightarrow f^*E$ in $Cov_Z$ since these categores are equivalent.



    Finally, according to (3.2.8) the isotropy subgroup of $xin E_{f(z)}$ is exactly the image of $p_*:pi_1(E,x)rightarrow pi_1(B,f(z))$, so putting everything together, $(f^*E)_zcong{z}times E_{f(z)}$ will have a fixed point under the $pi_1(Z,z)$ action whenever $f_*(pi_1(Z,z))subseteq p_*pi_1(E,x)$. Hence the conditions are sufficente to choose a section $zmapsto (z,e)$ of $f^*E$, which by the previous is equivalent to a lifting $Phi:Zrightarrow E$, satisfying $Phi(z)=x$.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$













    • $begingroup$
      Wow, so the section actually comes from the equvalence of categories! Now I see what he's talking about. Thanks for the inspiring answer! (BTW, I'd consider this proof somewhat flawed since the direct proof does not assume $Z$ is semi-locally simply connected.)
      $endgroup$
      – Colescu
      Dec 10 '18 at 0:45
















    3












    $begingroup$

    Form the pullback $f^*E=Ztimes_BE$. This space sits in a strictly commutative diagram
    $require{AMScd}$
    begin{CD}
    f^*E=Ztimes_BE@>k>> E\
    @VVq V @VV p V\
    Z @>f>> B
    end{CD}

    and has the universal property that for any space $A$ the projections $q,k$ induce a 1-1 correspondence



    $${text{maps}: Arightarrow Ztimes_BE}leftrightarrows{text{pairs};(a:Arightarrow Z, b:Arightarrow E)mid fcirc a=pcirc b}.$$



    Explicitly we send $F:Arightarrow Ztimes_BE$ to the pair $(qcirc F,kcirc F)$. The pullback is characterised by this universal property and so is unique up to homeomorphism. If you like you can take the standard model



    $$Ztimes_BE={(z,e)in Ztimes Emid f(z)=p(e)}subseteq Ztimes E,$$



    with the maps $q,k$ induced by projection onto each factor. In this way we make explicit the inverse to previous function: if $a:Arightarrow Z$, $b:Arightarrow E$ satisfy $fcirc a=pcirc b$ then we define $atimes_Bb:Arightarrow Ztimes_BE$ by $(atimes_Bb)(x)=(a(x),b(x))$, $xin A$. One check that this is well-defined and continuous.



    In this way we get the correspondence between liftings of $f$ and sections of $q:Ztimes_BErightarrow Z$. If $Phi:Zrightarrow E$ lifts $f$ through $p$ then it satisfies $pcirc Phi=f$, and so the pair $(id_Z,Phi)$, which lives on the right-hand side of the previous correspondence, induces a map $s_Phi:Zrightarrow Ztimes_BE$ which will satisfy



    $$qcirc s_Phi=id_Z,qquad kcirc s_Phi=Phi.$$



    In particular the first of these conditions shows that $s_Phi$ is a section of $q$.



    On the other hand, if $s:Zrightarrow Ztimes_BE$ is a section of $q$ then $Phi_s=kcirc s:Zrightarrow E$ lifts $f$. To wit,



    $$pcirc Phi_s=pcirc (kcirc s)=(pcirc k)circ s=(fcirc q)circ s=fcirc (qcirc s)=fcirc id_z=f.$$



    As for the condition $Phi_s(z)=x$ we observe that the fibre of $q$ over $a$ is homeomorphic to the fibre of $p$ of $f(z)$, the maps in the defining commutative square inducing the isomorphism. In fact using the explicit model gives us



    $$(Ztimes_BE)_z={(z,e)mid f(z)=p(e)}cong {z}times E_{f(z)}.$$



    Thus the requirement $Phi_s(z)=x$ is equivalent to the condition $s(z)=(z,x)$. From here one proceeds directly as in the given proof of (3.5.2) to get the result.



    However, I think you are after a more extended discussion, especially relating to the exercise [3.5.1]. For this, I belive that tom Dieck is interested in the case that both $B$ and $Z$ are path connected, locally path connected and semi-locally simply connected, so I will assume these additional hypotheses.



    Thus by (3.3.2) Classification I, and (3.4.1), the category of coverings $Cov_Z$ of $Z$ is equivalent to the category of $pi_zmbox-Set$ of (left) $pi_z=pi_1(Z,z)$-sets, where $zin Z$ is a chosen element. Above we have produced a pullback covering $q:f^*E=Ztimes_BErightarrow Z$ over $Z$, and this therefore corresponds to some $pi_z$-set which we'll denote $f^*mathcal{E}$. In fact we can see explicitly what this set is by what I have written above. The covering $p:Erightarrow B$ corresponds in $pi_{f(z)}$-set to the $pi_1(B,f(z))$-set given by the fibre $E_{f(z)}$. Therefore its pullback $f^*mathcal{E}$ should correspond to the $pi_z$-set given by the fibre



    $$(f^*E)_zcong {z}times E_{f(z)},$$



    and $pi_1(Z,z)$ should act on this set by the pullback action, that is,



    $$alphacdot (z,e)=(z,(f_*alpha)cdot e),qquad (z,e)in f^*E,alphainpi_1(Z,z).$$



    Now we can view a section $s:Zrightarrow f^*E$ of the pullback as a morphism of covering spaces
    $require{AMScd}$
    begin{CD}
    Z@>s>> f^*E\
    @VV= V @VV q V\
    Z @>=>> Z,
    end{CD}

    and this corresponds to a morphism $mathfrak{s}:{z}rightarrow f^*mathcal{E}$ in $pi_z$-Set . Here I have used that the trivial covering $id_Z:Zrightarrow Z$ with one-point fibres corresponds to the trivial one-point $pi_z$-set ${z}$. Such a $pi_1$-equivariant morphism $mathfrak{s}$ must take the $pi_z$-fixed element $z$ into an element of $f^*mathcal{E}$ which is fixed under the pullback $pi_z$-action. This is exactly the statement that $E_{f(z)}$ has a fixed point under the $pi_1(Z,z)$-action.



    On the other hand, if $kin f^*mathcal{E}$ is fixed by the pullback $pi_z$-action, then $mathfrak{s}:{z}rightarrow f^*mathcal{E}$, $ymapsto k$, is well-defined in $pi_z$-Set and so gives rise to a section $s:Zrightarrow f^*E$ in $Cov_Z$ since these categores are equivalent.



    Finally, according to (3.2.8) the isotropy subgroup of $xin E_{f(z)}$ is exactly the image of $p_*:pi_1(E,x)rightarrow pi_1(B,f(z))$, so putting everything together, $(f^*E)_zcong{z}times E_{f(z)}$ will have a fixed point under the $pi_1(Z,z)$ action whenever $f_*(pi_1(Z,z))subseteq p_*pi_1(E,x)$. Hence the conditions are sufficente to choose a section $zmapsto (z,e)$ of $f^*E$, which by the previous is equivalent to a lifting $Phi:Zrightarrow E$, satisfying $Phi(z)=x$.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$













    • $begingroup$
      Wow, so the section actually comes from the equvalence of categories! Now I see what he's talking about. Thanks for the inspiring answer! (BTW, I'd consider this proof somewhat flawed since the direct proof does not assume $Z$ is semi-locally simply connected.)
      $endgroup$
      – Colescu
      Dec 10 '18 at 0:45














    3












    3








    3





    $begingroup$

    Form the pullback $f^*E=Ztimes_BE$. This space sits in a strictly commutative diagram
    $require{AMScd}$
    begin{CD}
    f^*E=Ztimes_BE@>k>> E\
    @VVq V @VV p V\
    Z @>f>> B
    end{CD}

    and has the universal property that for any space $A$ the projections $q,k$ induce a 1-1 correspondence



    $${text{maps}: Arightarrow Ztimes_BE}leftrightarrows{text{pairs};(a:Arightarrow Z, b:Arightarrow E)mid fcirc a=pcirc b}.$$



    Explicitly we send $F:Arightarrow Ztimes_BE$ to the pair $(qcirc F,kcirc F)$. The pullback is characterised by this universal property and so is unique up to homeomorphism. If you like you can take the standard model



    $$Ztimes_BE={(z,e)in Ztimes Emid f(z)=p(e)}subseteq Ztimes E,$$



    with the maps $q,k$ induced by projection onto each factor. In this way we make explicit the inverse to previous function: if $a:Arightarrow Z$, $b:Arightarrow E$ satisfy $fcirc a=pcirc b$ then we define $atimes_Bb:Arightarrow Ztimes_BE$ by $(atimes_Bb)(x)=(a(x),b(x))$, $xin A$. One check that this is well-defined and continuous.



    In this way we get the correspondence between liftings of $f$ and sections of $q:Ztimes_BErightarrow Z$. If $Phi:Zrightarrow E$ lifts $f$ through $p$ then it satisfies $pcirc Phi=f$, and so the pair $(id_Z,Phi)$, which lives on the right-hand side of the previous correspondence, induces a map $s_Phi:Zrightarrow Ztimes_BE$ which will satisfy



    $$qcirc s_Phi=id_Z,qquad kcirc s_Phi=Phi.$$



    In particular the first of these conditions shows that $s_Phi$ is a section of $q$.



    On the other hand, if $s:Zrightarrow Ztimes_BE$ is a section of $q$ then $Phi_s=kcirc s:Zrightarrow E$ lifts $f$. To wit,



    $$pcirc Phi_s=pcirc (kcirc s)=(pcirc k)circ s=(fcirc q)circ s=fcirc (qcirc s)=fcirc id_z=f.$$



    As for the condition $Phi_s(z)=x$ we observe that the fibre of $q$ over $a$ is homeomorphic to the fibre of $p$ of $f(z)$, the maps in the defining commutative square inducing the isomorphism. In fact using the explicit model gives us



    $$(Ztimes_BE)_z={(z,e)mid f(z)=p(e)}cong {z}times E_{f(z)}.$$



    Thus the requirement $Phi_s(z)=x$ is equivalent to the condition $s(z)=(z,x)$. From here one proceeds directly as in the given proof of (3.5.2) to get the result.



    However, I think you are after a more extended discussion, especially relating to the exercise [3.5.1]. For this, I belive that tom Dieck is interested in the case that both $B$ and $Z$ are path connected, locally path connected and semi-locally simply connected, so I will assume these additional hypotheses.



    Thus by (3.3.2) Classification I, and (3.4.1), the category of coverings $Cov_Z$ of $Z$ is equivalent to the category of $pi_zmbox-Set$ of (left) $pi_z=pi_1(Z,z)$-sets, where $zin Z$ is a chosen element. Above we have produced a pullback covering $q:f^*E=Ztimes_BErightarrow Z$ over $Z$, and this therefore corresponds to some $pi_z$-set which we'll denote $f^*mathcal{E}$. In fact we can see explicitly what this set is by what I have written above. The covering $p:Erightarrow B$ corresponds in $pi_{f(z)}$-set to the $pi_1(B,f(z))$-set given by the fibre $E_{f(z)}$. Therefore its pullback $f^*mathcal{E}$ should correspond to the $pi_z$-set given by the fibre



    $$(f^*E)_zcong {z}times E_{f(z)},$$



    and $pi_1(Z,z)$ should act on this set by the pullback action, that is,



    $$alphacdot (z,e)=(z,(f_*alpha)cdot e),qquad (z,e)in f^*E,alphainpi_1(Z,z).$$



    Now we can view a section $s:Zrightarrow f^*E$ of the pullback as a morphism of covering spaces
    $require{AMScd}$
    begin{CD}
    Z@>s>> f^*E\
    @VV= V @VV q V\
    Z @>=>> Z,
    end{CD}

    and this corresponds to a morphism $mathfrak{s}:{z}rightarrow f^*mathcal{E}$ in $pi_z$-Set . Here I have used that the trivial covering $id_Z:Zrightarrow Z$ with one-point fibres corresponds to the trivial one-point $pi_z$-set ${z}$. Such a $pi_1$-equivariant morphism $mathfrak{s}$ must take the $pi_z$-fixed element $z$ into an element of $f^*mathcal{E}$ which is fixed under the pullback $pi_z$-action. This is exactly the statement that $E_{f(z)}$ has a fixed point under the $pi_1(Z,z)$-action.



    On the other hand, if $kin f^*mathcal{E}$ is fixed by the pullback $pi_z$-action, then $mathfrak{s}:{z}rightarrow f^*mathcal{E}$, $ymapsto k$, is well-defined in $pi_z$-Set and so gives rise to a section $s:Zrightarrow f^*E$ in $Cov_Z$ since these categores are equivalent.



    Finally, according to (3.2.8) the isotropy subgroup of $xin E_{f(z)}$ is exactly the image of $p_*:pi_1(E,x)rightarrow pi_1(B,f(z))$, so putting everything together, $(f^*E)_zcong{z}times E_{f(z)}$ will have a fixed point under the $pi_1(Z,z)$ action whenever $f_*(pi_1(Z,z))subseteq p_*pi_1(E,x)$. Hence the conditions are sufficente to choose a section $zmapsto (z,e)$ of $f^*E$, which by the previous is equivalent to a lifting $Phi:Zrightarrow E$, satisfying $Phi(z)=x$.






    share|cite|improve this answer









    $endgroup$



    Form the pullback $f^*E=Ztimes_BE$. This space sits in a strictly commutative diagram
    $require{AMScd}$
    begin{CD}
    f^*E=Ztimes_BE@>k>> E\
    @VVq V @VV p V\
    Z @>f>> B
    end{CD}

    and has the universal property that for any space $A$ the projections $q,k$ induce a 1-1 correspondence



    $${text{maps}: Arightarrow Ztimes_BE}leftrightarrows{text{pairs};(a:Arightarrow Z, b:Arightarrow E)mid fcirc a=pcirc b}.$$



    Explicitly we send $F:Arightarrow Ztimes_BE$ to the pair $(qcirc F,kcirc F)$. The pullback is characterised by this universal property and so is unique up to homeomorphism. If you like you can take the standard model



    $$Ztimes_BE={(z,e)in Ztimes Emid f(z)=p(e)}subseteq Ztimes E,$$



    with the maps $q,k$ induced by projection onto each factor. In this way we make explicit the inverse to previous function: if $a:Arightarrow Z$, $b:Arightarrow E$ satisfy $fcirc a=pcirc b$ then we define $atimes_Bb:Arightarrow Ztimes_BE$ by $(atimes_Bb)(x)=(a(x),b(x))$, $xin A$. One check that this is well-defined and continuous.



    In this way we get the correspondence between liftings of $f$ and sections of $q:Ztimes_BErightarrow Z$. If $Phi:Zrightarrow E$ lifts $f$ through $p$ then it satisfies $pcirc Phi=f$, and so the pair $(id_Z,Phi)$, which lives on the right-hand side of the previous correspondence, induces a map $s_Phi:Zrightarrow Ztimes_BE$ which will satisfy



    $$qcirc s_Phi=id_Z,qquad kcirc s_Phi=Phi.$$



    In particular the first of these conditions shows that $s_Phi$ is a section of $q$.



    On the other hand, if $s:Zrightarrow Ztimes_BE$ is a section of $q$ then $Phi_s=kcirc s:Zrightarrow E$ lifts $f$. To wit,



    $$pcirc Phi_s=pcirc (kcirc s)=(pcirc k)circ s=(fcirc q)circ s=fcirc (qcirc s)=fcirc id_z=f.$$



    As for the condition $Phi_s(z)=x$ we observe that the fibre of $q$ over $a$ is homeomorphic to the fibre of $p$ of $f(z)$, the maps in the defining commutative square inducing the isomorphism. In fact using the explicit model gives us



    $$(Ztimes_BE)_z={(z,e)mid f(z)=p(e)}cong {z}times E_{f(z)}.$$



    Thus the requirement $Phi_s(z)=x$ is equivalent to the condition $s(z)=(z,x)$. From here one proceeds directly as in the given proof of (3.5.2) to get the result.



    However, I think you are after a more extended discussion, especially relating to the exercise [3.5.1]. For this, I belive that tom Dieck is interested in the case that both $B$ and $Z$ are path connected, locally path connected and semi-locally simply connected, so I will assume these additional hypotheses.



    Thus by (3.3.2) Classification I, and (3.4.1), the category of coverings $Cov_Z$ of $Z$ is equivalent to the category of $pi_zmbox-Set$ of (left) $pi_z=pi_1(Z,z)$-sets, where $zin Z$ is a chosen element. Above we have produced a pullback covering $q:f^*E=Ztimes_BErightarrow Z$ over $Z$, and this therefore corresponds to some $pi_z$-set which we'll denote $f^*mathcal{E}$. In fact we can see explicitly what this set is by what I have written above. The covering $p:Erightarrow B$ corresponds in $pi_{f(z)}$-set to the $pi_1(B,f(z))$-set given by the fibre $E_{f(z)}$. Therefore its pullback $f^*mathcal{E}$ should correspond to the $pi_z$-set given by the fibre



    $$(f^*E)_zcong {z}times E_{f(z)},$$



    and $pi_1(Z,z)$ should act on this set by the pullback action, that is,



    $$alphacdot (z,e)=(z,(f_*alpha)cdot e),qquad (z,e)in f^*E,alphainpi_1(Z,z).$$



    Now we can view a section $s:Zrightarrow f^*E$ of the pullback as a morphism of covering spaces
    $require{AMScd}$
    begin{CD}
    Z@>s>> f^*E\
    @VV= V @VV q V\
    Z @>=>> Z,
    end{CD}

    and this corresponds to a morphism $mathfrak{s}:{z}rightarrow f^*mathcal{E}$ in $pi_z$-Set . Here I have used that the trivial covering $id_Z:Zrightarrow Z$ with one-point fibres corresponds to the trivial one-point $pi_z$-set ${z}$. Such a $pi_1$-equivariant morphism $mathfrak{s}$ must take the $pi_z$-fixed element $z$ into an element of $f^*mathcal{E}$ which is fixed under the pullback $pi_z$-action. This is exactly the statement that $E_{f(z)}$ has a fixed point under the $pi_1(Z,z)$-action.



    On the other hand, if $kin f^*mathcal{E}$ is fixed by the pullback $pi_z$-action, then $mathfrak{s}:{z}rightarrow f^*mathcal{E}$, $ymapsto k$, is well-defined in $pi_z$-Set and so gives rise to a section $s:Zrightarrow f^*E$ in $Cov_Z$ since these categores are equivalent.



    Finally, according to (3.2.8) the isotropy subgroup of $xin E_{f(z)}$ is exactly the image of $p_*:pi_1(E,x)rightarrow pi_1(B,f(z))$, so putting everything together, $(f^*E)_zcong{z}times E_{f(z)}$ will have a fixed point under the $pi_1(Z,z)$ action whenever $f_*(pi_1(Z,z))subseteq p_*pi_1(E,x)$. Hence the conditions are sufficente to choose a section $zmapsto (z,e)$ of $f^*E$, which by the previous is equivalent to a lifting $Phi:Zrightarrow E$, satisfying $Phi(z)=x$.







    share|cite|improve this answer












    share|cite|improve this answer



    share|cite|improve this answer










    answered Dec 9 '18 at 16:31









    TyroneTyrone

    4,55011225




    4,55011225












    • $begingroup$
      Wow, so the section actually comes from the equvalence of categories! Now I see what he's talking about. Thanks for the inspiring answer! (BTW, I'd consider this proof somewhat flawed since the direct proof does not assume $Z$ is semi-locally simply connected.)
      $endgroup$
      – Colescu
      Dec 10 '18 at 0:45


















    • $begingroup$
      Wow, so the section actually comes from the equvalence of categories! Now I see what he's talking about. Thanks for the inspiring answer! (BTW, I'd consider this proof somewhat flawed since the direct proof does not assume $Z$ is semi-locally simply connected.)
      $endgroup$
      – Colescu
      Dec 10 '18 at 0:45
















    $begingroup$
    Wow, so the section actually comes from the equvalence of categories! Now I see what he's talking about. Thanks for the inspiring answer! (BTW, I'd consider this proof somewhat flawed since the direct proof does not assume $Z$ is semi-locally simply connected.)
    $endgroup$
    – Colescu
    Dec 10 '18 at 0:45




    $begingroup$
    Wow, so the section actually comes from the equvalence of categories! Now I see what he's talking about. Thanks for the inspiring answer! (BTW, I'd consider this proof somewhat flawed since the direct proof does not assume $Z$ is semi-locally simply connected.)
    $endgroup$
    – Colescu
    Dec 10 '18 at 0:45











    1












    $begingroup$

    I just found a simpler proof that works without the hypothesis that $B$ is semi-locally simply connected (and therefore without using sophisticated results on the classification of covering spaces for such spaces). Moreover, I think it is closer to what the author had in mind.



    First, for any covering $p:Eto B$, we have the transport functor $T_p:Pi(B)tomathsf{SET}$, where $T_p(b)=p^{-1}(b)$ for $bin B$, and for $v:Ito B$ the map $T_p(v):p^{-1}(v(0))to p^{-1}(v(1))$ is defined thus: given $ein p^{-1}(v(0))$ lift $v$ to $V:Ito E$ (i.e., $pV=v$) with initial condition $V(0)=e$ and set $[T_p(v)](e):=V(1)$. (This is introduced on page 67 of tom Dieck's book.)



    The proof begins. We use the pushout
    begin{CD}
    Y @>k>> E\
    @V V q V @V V p V\
    Z @>>f> B
    end{CD}

    where $Y:={,(z,x)in Ztimes E:f(z)=p(x),}$ and $q,k$ are projections onto the coordinates. Then $q$ is also a covering. This induces transport functors $T_p:Pi(B)tomathsf{SET}$, $T_q:Pi(Z)tomathsf{SET}.$ Now observe that $T_q(z)={z}times p^{-1}(f(z))cong T_p(f(z))$ and this is a natural equivalence $eta:T_qsimeq T_pcircPi(f)$. (This is actually Problem 3.3.2 in disguise.) In particular we have a commutative diagram
    begin{CD}
    q^{-1}(z) @>eta_z>> p^{-1}(f(z))\
    @V V T_q(v) V @V V T_p(fv) V\
    q^{-1}(z) @>>eta_z> p^{-1}(f(z))
    end{CD}

    where $vinpi_1(Z,z)$. Thus $pi_1(Z,z)$ acts on $p^{-1}(f(z))$ if we identify $q^{-1}(z)$ and $p^{-1}(f(z))$ via $eta$.



    The condition $f_*(pi_1(Z,z))subset p_*(pi_1(E,x))$ says $pi_1(Z,z)$ fixes $x$. So $q_*:pi_1(Y,(z,x))topi_1(Z,z)$ is an isomorphism. (tom Dieck, page 69, Proposition 3.2.8) If we take the component $Y_0$ of $Y$ containing $(z,x)$, then $q_0:=qmid_{Y_0}:Y_0to Z$ is a covering (tom Dieck, page 64, Remark 3.1.6; local path connectedness is used here) with fiber consisting of a single point, i.e., $q_0$ is a homeomorphism. (This gives the section mentioned in the exercise.) Finally, $kq_0^{-1}$ gives the desired lifting.






    share|cite|improve this answer











    $endgroup$


















      1












      $begingroup$

      I just found a simpler proof that works without the hypothesis that $B$ is semi-locally simply connected (and therefore without using sophisticated results on the classification of covering spaces for such spaces). Moreover, I think it is closer to what the author had in mind.



      First, for any covering $p:Eto B$, we have the transport functor $T_p:Pi(B)tomathsf{SET}$, where $T_p(b)=p^{-1}(b)$ for $bin B$, and for $v:Ito B$ the map $T_p(v):p^{-1}(v(0))to p^{-1}(v(1))$ is defined thus: given $ein p^{-1}(v(0))$ lift $v$ to $V:Ito E$ (i.e., $pV=v$) with initial condition $V(0)=e$ and set $[T_p(v)](e):=V(1)$. (This is introduced on page 67 of tom Dieck's book.)



      The proof begins. We use the pushout
      begin{CD}
      Y @>k>> E\
      @V V q V @V V p V\
      Z @>>f> B
      end{CD}

      where $Y:={,(z,x)in Ztimes E:f(z)=p(x),}$ and $q,k$ are projections onto the coordinates. Then $q$ is also a covering. This induces transport functors $T_p:Pi(B)tomathsf{SET}$, $T_q:Pi(Z)tomathsf{SET}.$ Now observe that $T_q(z)={z}times p^{-1}(f(z))cong T_p(f(z))$ and this is a natural equivalence $eta:T_qsimeq T_pcircPi(f)$. (This is actually Problem 3.3.2 in disguise.) In particular we have a commutative diagram
      begin{CD}
      q^{-1}(z) @>eta_z>> p^{-1}(f(z))\
      @V V T_q(v) V @V V T_p(fv) V\
      q^{-1}(z) @>>eta_z> p^{-1}(f(z))
      end{CD}

      where $vinpi_1(Z,z)$. Thus $pi_1(Z,z)$ acts on $p^{-1}(f(z))$ if we identify $q^{-1}(z)$ and $p^{-1}(f(z))$ via $eta$.



      The condition $f_*(pi_1(Z,z))subset p_*(pi_1(E,x))$ says $pi_1(Z,z)$ fixes $x$. So $q_*:pi_1(Y,(z,x))topi_1(Z,z)$ is an isomorphism. (tom Dieck, page 69, Proposition 3.2.8) If we take the component $Y_0$ of $Y$ containing $(z,x)$, then $q_0:=qmid_{Y_0}:Y_0to Z$ is a covering (tom Dieck, page 64, Remark 3.1.6; local path connectedness is used here) with fiber consisting of a single point, i.e., $q_0$ is a homeomorphism. (This gives the section mentioned in the exercise.) Finally, $kq_0^{-1}$ gives the desired lifting.






      share|cite|improve this answer











      $endgroup$
















        1












        1








        1





        $begingroup$

        I just found a simpler proof that works without the hypothesis that $B$ is semi-locally simply connected (and therefore without using sophisticated results on the classification of covering spaces for such spaces). Moreover, I think it is closer to what the author had in mind.



        First, for any covering $p:Eto B$, we have the transport functor $T_p:Pi(B)tomathsf{SET}$, where $T_p(b)=p^{-1}(b)$ for $bin B$, and for $v:Ito B$ the map $T_p(v):p^{-1}(v(0))to p^{-1}(v(1))$ is defined thus: given $ein p^{-1}(v(0))$ lift $v$ to $V:Ito E$ (i.e., $pV=v$) with initial condition $V(0)=e$ and set $[T_p(v)](e):=V(1)$. (This is introduced on page 67 of tom Dieck's book.)



        The proof begins. We use the pushout
        begin{CD}
        Y @>k>> E\
        @V V q V @V V p V\
        Z @>>f> B
        end{CD}

        where $Y:={,(z,x)in Ztimes E:f(z)=p(x),}$ and $q,k$ are projections onto the coordinates. Then $q$ is also a covering. This induces transport functors $T_p:Pi(B)tomathsf{SET}$, $T_q:Pi(Z)tomathsf{SET}.$ Now observe that $T_q(z)={z}times p^{-1}(f(z))cong T_p(f(z))$ and this is a natural equivalence $eta:T_qsimeq T_pcircPi(f)$. (This is actually Problem 3.3.2 in disguise.) In particular we have a commutative diagram
        begin{CD}
        q^{-1}(z) @>eta_z>> p^{-1}(f(z))\
        @V V T_q(v) V @V V T_p(fv) V\
        q^{-1}(z) @>>eta_z> p^{-1}(f(z))
        end{CD}

        where $vinpi_1(Z,z)$. Thus $pi_1(Z,z)$ acts on $p^{-1}(f(z))$ if we identify $q^{-1}(z)$ and $p^{-1}(f(z))$ via $eta$.



        The condition $f_*(pi_1(Z,z))subset p_*(pi_1(E,x))$ says $pi_1(Z,z)$ fixes $x$. So $q_*:pi_1(Y,(z,x))topi_1(Z,z)$ is an isomorphism. (tom Dieck, page 69, Proposition 3.2.8) If we take the component $Y_0$ of $Y$ containing $(z,x)$, then $q_0:=qmid_{Y_0}:Y_0to Z$ is a covering (tom Dieck, page 64, Remark 3.1.6; local path connectedness is used here) with fiber consisting of a single point, i.e., $q_0$ is a homeomorphism. (This gives the section mentioned in the exercise.) Finally, $kq_0^{-1}$ gives the desired lifting.






        share|cite|improve this answer











        $endgroup$



        I just found a simpler proof that works without the hypothesis that $B$ is semi-locally simply connected (and therefore without using sophisticated results on the classification of covering spaces for such spaces). Moreover, I think it is closer to what the author had in mind.



        First, for any covering $p:Eto B$, we have the transport functor $T_p:Pi(B)tomathsf{SET}$, where $T_p(b)=p^{-1}(b)$ for $bin B$, and for $v:Ito B$ the map $T_p(v):p^{-1}(v(0))to p^{-1}(v(1))$ is defined thus: given $ein p^{-1}(v(0))$ lift $v$ to $V:Ito E$ (i.e., $pV=v$) with initial condition $V(0)=e$ and set $[T_p(v)](e):=V(1)$. (This is introduced on page 67 of tom Dieck's book.)



        The proof begins. We use the pushout
        begin{CD}
        Y @>k>> E\
        @V V q V @V V p V\
        Z @>>f> B
        end{CD}

        where $Y:={,(z,x)in Ztimes E:f(z)=p(x),}$ and $q,k$ are projections onto the coordinates. Then $q$ is also a covering. This induces transport functors $T_p:Pi(B)tomathsf{SET}$, $T_q:Pi(Z)tomathsf{SET}.$ Now observe that $T_q(z)={z}times p^{-1}(f(z))cong T_p(f(z))$ and this is a natural equivalence $eta:T_qsimeq T_pcircPi(f)$. (This is actually Problem 3.3.2 in disguise.) In particular we have a commutative diagram
        begin{CD}
        q^{-1}(z) @>eta_z>> p^{-1}(f(z))\
        @V V T_q(v) V @V V T_p(fv) V\
        q^{-1}(z) @>>eta_z> p^{-1}(f(z))
        end{CD}

        where $vinpi_1(Z,z)$. Thus $pi_1(Z,z)$ acts on $p^{-1}(f(z))$ if we identify $q^{-1}(z)$ and $p^{-1}(f(z))$ via $eta$.



        The condition $f_*(pi_1(Z,z))subset p_*(pi_1(E,x))$ says $pi_1(Z,z)$ fixes $x$. So $q_*:pi_1(Y,(z,x))topi_1(Z,z)$ is an isomorphism. (tom Dieck, page 69, Proposition 3.2.8) If we take the component $Y_0$ of $Y$ containing $(z,x)$, then $q_0:=qmid_{Y_0}:Y_0to Z$ is a covering (tom Dieck, page 64, Remark 3.1.6; local path connectedness is used here) with fiber consisting of a single point, i.e., $q_0$ is a homeomorphism. (This gives the section mentioned in the exercise.) Finally, $kq_0^{-1}$ gives the desired lifting.







        share|cite|improve this answer














        share|cite|improve this answer



        share|cite|improve this answer








        edited Dec 26 '18 at 14:21

























        answered Dec 24 '18 at 5:47









        ColescuColescu

        3,0951736




        3,0951736






























            draft saved

            draft discarded




















































            Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!


            • Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!

            But avoid



            • Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.

            • Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.


            Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.


            To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.




            draft saved


            draft discarded














            StackExchange.ready(
            function () {
            StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f3031092%2fan-alternative-more-formal-proof-of-a-path-lifting-criterion-in-tom-diecks-alg%23new-answer', 'question_page');
            }
            );

            Post as a guest















            Required, but never shown





















































            Required, but never shown














            Required, but never shown












            Required, but never shown







            Required, but never shown

































            Required, but never shown














            Required, but never shown












            Required, but never shown







            Required, but never shown







            Popular posts from this blog

            Wiesbaden

            Marschland

            Dieringhausen