Minimal model of ZF with $0sharp$
up vote
3
down vote
favorite
We know that the constructible universe $L$ is an absolute and minimal model of ZF (every standard model of ZF contains "an" $L$, and it is actually the same $L$ for all of them).
It is also my understanding that the existence of $0sharp$ informally means that $V$ is much "bigger" than $L$ (meaning that if $0sharp$ exists then even $aleph_1$ is already an inaccessible cardinal in $L$) and that a sort of converse is true (see: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Jensen%27s_covering_theorem).
Therefore my question is: Is there an absolute minimal model of ZF + $exists0sharp$ ?
A sort of "$Lsharp$" if we really want to abuse notation?
logic set-theory model-theory large-cardinals
|
show 1 more comment
up vote
3
down vote
favorite
We know that the constructible universe $L$ is an absolute and minimal model of ZF (every standard model of ZF contains "an" $L$, and it is actually the same $L$ for all of them).
It is also my understanding that the existence of $0sharp$ informally means that $V$ is much "bigger" than $L$ (meaning that if $0sharp$ exists then even $aleph_1$ is already an inaccessible cardinal in $L$) and that a sort of converse is true (see: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Jensen%27s_covering_theorem).
Therefore my question is: Is there an absolute minimal model of ZF + $exists0sharp$ ?
A sort of "$Lsharp$" if we really want to abuse notation?
logic set-theory model-theory large-cardinals
4
Sure. The model is denoted $L[0^sharp]$. You mimic the construction of $L$, but allow in your language a predicate for $0^sharp$ (understood as a set of numbers).
– Andrés E. Caicedo
Feb 28 '16 at 0:18
Isn't $L(0sharp)$ smaller?
– Alon Navon
Feb 28 '16 at 0:26
4
We have $L[0^sharp] = L(0^sharp)$: In general, for any given set $A$, we have $L[A] subseteq L(A)$ with equalitiy if and only if $A cap L[A] = A$. Since $0^sharp$ may be regarded as a subset of $omega$, we have $0^sharp subseteq L subseteq L[0^sharp]$ and thus the claimed equality.
– Stefan Mesken
Feb 28 '16 at 0:38
1
@Stefan Thank you very much, I got my relative constructibility all mixed up, and you cleared a lot. :) This means in essence that we can define a "sharp" sequence. $L_0 = L$, $L_1 = L[0^sharp]$, $L_2 = L[0^{sharpsharp}]$, etc... Just wondering whether there is any use for this? Any other nice properties that make these "L's" "L-ish"?
– Alon Navon
Feb 28 '16 at 0:49
3
Well, $L[A]$ is similar to $L$ in a lot of ways - a major reason for this is, that the usual condensation lemma generalizes to $L[A]$ (which allows us to prove $operatorname{GCH}$, $Diamond_kappa$, $square_kappa$, ... on a "tail segment" of $L[A]$).
– Stefan Mesken
Feb 28 '16 at 1:19
|
show 1 more comment
up vote
3
down vote
favorite
up vote
3
down vote
favorite
We know that the constructible universe $L$ is an absolute and minimal model of ZF (every standard model of ZF contains "an" $L$, and it is actually the same $L$ for all of them).
It is also my understanding that the existence of $0sharp$ informally means that $V$ is much "bigger" than $L$ (meaning that if $0sharp$ exists then even $aleph_1$ is already an inaccessible cardinal in $L$) and that a sort of converse is true (see: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Jensen%27s_covering_theorem).
Therefore my question is: Is there an absolute minimal model of ZF + $exists0sharp$ ?
A sort of "$Lsharp$" if we really want to abuse notation?
logic set-theory model-theory large-cardinals
We know that the constructible universe $L$ is an absolute and minimal model of ZF (every standard model of ZF contains "an" $L$, and it is actually the same $L$ for all of them).
It is also my understanding that the existence of $0sharp$ informally means that $V$ is much "bigger" than $L$ (meaning that if $0sharp$ exists then even $aleph_1$ is already an inaccessible cardinal in $L$) and that a sort of converse is true (see: https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Jensen%27s_covering_theorem).
Therefore my question is: Is there an absolute minimal model of ZF + $exists0sharp$ ?
A sort of "$Lsharp$" if we really want to abuse notation?
logic set-theory model-theory large-cardinals
logic set-theory model-theory large-cardinals
asked Feb 28 '16 at 0:12
Alon Navon
1,025413
1,025413
4
Sure. The model is denoted $L[0^sharp]$. You mimic the construction of $L$, but allow in your language a predicate for $0^sharp$ (understood as a set of numbers).
– Andrés E. Caicedo
Feb 28 '16 at 0:18
Isn't $L(0sharp)$ smaller?
– Alon Navon
Feb 28 '16 at 0:26
4
We have $L[0^sharp] = L(0^sharp)$: In general, for any given set $A$, we have $L[A] subseteq L(A)$ with equalitiy if and only if $A cap L[A] = A$. Since $0^sharp$ may be regarded as a subset of $omega$, we have $0^sharp subseteq L subseteq L[0^sharp]$ and thus the claimed equality.
– Stefan Mesken
Feb 28 '16 at 0:38
1
@Stefan Thank you very much, I got my relative constructibility all mixed up, and you cleared a lot. :) This means in essence that we can define a "sharp" sequence. $L_0 = L$, $L_1 = L[0^sharp]$, $L_2 = L[0^{sharpsharp}]$, etc... Just wondering whether there is any use for this? Any other nice properties that make these "L's" "L-ish"?
– Alon Navon
Feb 28 '16 at 0:49
3
Well, $L[A]$ is similar to $L$ in a lot of ways - a major reason for this is, that the usual condensation lemma generalizes to $L[A]$ (which allows us to prove $operatorname{GCH}$, $Diamond_kappa$, $square_kappa$, ... on a "tail segment" of $L[A]$).
– Stefan Mesken
Feb 28 '16 at 1:19
|
show 1 more comment
4
Sure. The model is denoted $L[0^sharp]$. You mimic the construction of $L$, but allow in your language a predicate for $0^sharp$ (understood as a set of numbers).
– Andrés E. Caicedo
Feb 28 '16 at 0:18
Isn't $L(0sharp)$ smaller?
– Alon Navon
Feb 28 '16 at 0:26
4
We have $L[0^sharp] = L(0^sharp)$: In general, for any given set $A$, we have $L[A] subseteq L(A)$ with equalitiy if and only if $A cap L[A] = A$. Since $0^sharp$ may be regarded as a subset of $omega$, we have $0^sharp subseteq L subseteq L[0^sharp]$ and thus the claimed equality.
– Stefan Mesken
Feb 28 '16 at 0:38
1
@Stefan Thank you very much, I got my relative constructibility all mixed up, and you cleared a lot. :) This means in essence that we can define a "sharp" sequence. $L_0 = L$, $L_1 = L[0^sharp]$, $L_2 = L[0^{sharpsharp}]$, etc... Just wondering whether there is any use for this? Any other nice properties that make these "L's" "L-ish"?
– Alon Navon
Feb 28 '16 at 0:49
3
Well, $L[A]$ is similar to $L$ in a lot of ways - a major reason for this is, that the usual condensation lemma generalizes to $L[A]$ (which allows us to prove $operatorname{GCH}$, $Diamond_kappa$, $square_kappa$, ... on a "tail segment" of $L[A]$).
– Stefan Mesken
Feb 28 '16 at 1:19
4
4
Sure. The model is denoted $L[0^sharp]$. You mimic the construction of $L$, but allow in your language a predicate for $0^sharp$ (understood as a set of numbers).
– Andrés E. Caicedo
Feb 28 '16 at 0:18
Sure. The model is denoted $L[0^sharp]$. You mimic the construction of $L$, but allow in your language a predicate for $0^sharp$ (understood as a set of numbers).
– Andrés E. Caicedo
Feb 28 '16 at 0:18
Isn't $L(0sharp)$ smaller?
– Alon Navon
Feb 28 '16 at 0:26
Isn't $L(0sharp)$ smaller?
– Alon Navon
Feb 28 '16 at 0:26
4
4
We have $L[0^sharp] = L(0^sharp)$: In general, for any given set $A$, we have $L[A] subseteq L(A)$ with equalitiy if and only if $A cap L[A] = A$. Since $0^sharp$ may be regarded as a subset of $omega$, we have $0^sharp subseteq L subseteq L[0^sharp]$ and thus the claimed equality.
– Stefan Mesken
Feb 28 '16 at 0:38
We have $L[0^sharp] = L(0^sharp)$: In general, for any given set $A$, we have $L[A] subseteq L(A)$ with equalitiy if and only if $A cap L[A] = A$. Since $0^sharp$ may be regarded as a subset of $omega$, we have $0^sharp subseteq L subseteq L[0^sharp]$ and thus the claimed equality.
– Stefan Mesken
Feb 28 '16 at 0:38
1
1
@Stefan Thank you very much, I got my relative constructibility all mixed up, and you cleared a lot. :) This means in essence that we can define a "sharp" sequence. $L_0 = L$, $L_1 = L[0^sharp]$, $L_2 = L[0^{sharpsharp}]$, etc... Just wondering whether there is any use for this? Any other nice properties that make these "L's" "L-ish"?
– Alon Navon
Feb 28 '16 at 0:49
@Stefan Thank you very much, I got my relative constructibility all mixed up, and you cleared a lot. :) This means in essence that we can define a "sharp" sequence. $L_0 = L$, $L_1 = L[0^sharp]$, $L_2 = L[0^{sharpsharp}]$, etc... Just wondering whether there is any use for this? Any other nice properties that make these "L's" "L-ish"?
– Alon Navon
Feb 28 '16 at 0:49
3
3
Well, $L[A]$ is similar to $L$ in a lot of ways - a major reason for this is, that the usual condensation lemma generalizes to $L[A]$ (which allows us to prove $operatorname{GCH}$, $Diamond_kappa$, $square_kappa$, ... on a "tail segment" of $L[A]$).
– Stefan Mesken
Feb 28 '16 at 1:19
Well, $L[A]$ is similar to $L$ in a lot of ways - a major reason for this is, that the usual condensation lemma generalizes to $L[A]$ (which allows us to prove $operatorname{GCH}$, $Diamond_kappa$, $square_kappa$, ... on a "tail segment" of $L[A]$).
– Stefan Mesken
Feb 28 '16 at 1:19
|
show 1 more comment
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
up vote
3
down vote
accepted
Yes, the minimal such model is $L[0^sharp]$. This model can be built by stages, just as $L$, starting with the empty set, taking unions at limit stages, and at each successor stage $alpha+1$ taking the collection of subsets of $L_alpha[0^sharp]$ definable in $(L_alpha[0^sharp],in,0^sharp)$ from parameters. Here, $0^sharp$ can be thought of as a set of natural numbers, and definability is in the language of set theory with one additional predicate.
Note that for each finite $n$, $L_n[0^sharp]=L_n$ (that is, the universes of both structures coincide) and so $L_omega[0^sharp]=L_omega$. However, $0^sharp$ is now definable at this stage (as the set of numbers satisfying the new predicate), so $0^sharpin L[0^sharp]$.
This is not quite enough. Let $varphi(x)$ be the formula in the language of set theory stating that $x$ is $0^sharp$, i.e., stating that $x$ is the unique EM blueprint satisfying the three indiscernibility conditions listed in section 9 of
MR1994835 (2004f:03092) Kanamori, Akihiro. The higher infinite. Large cardinals in set theory from their beginnings. Second edition. Springer Monographs in Mathematics. Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 2003. xxii+536 pp. ISBN: 3-540-00384-3.
One should also check that $L[0^sharp]models varphi(0^sharp)$, and that whenever $M$ is an inner model and $Mmodelsvarphi(a)$ for some $a$, then $0^sharp$ exists in $V$ and $a=0^sharp$, so that $L[0^sharp]subseteq M$. This is essentially an absoluteness argument, but it is a bit technical so I will skip the details here. The point of proving this is that not only is $L[0^sharp]$ the smallest such model, but it knows it, in the sense that it satisfies $L[0^sharp]models V=L[0^sharp]$, and is contained in any inner model that believes in the existence of $0^sharp$.
One can prove more as well, for instance, $L[0^sharp]$ satisfies appropriate analogues of the fine structural properties of $L$, so it is not just the least model containing $0^sharp$, it is also a very well-behaved model. Naturally, the construction generalizes to more general sharps and other inner-model theoretic objects, although the absoluteness requirements become more involved.
add a comment |
Your Answer
StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
});
});
}, "mathjax-editing");
StackExchange.ready(function() {
var channelOptions = {
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
};
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);
StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
createEditor();
});
}
else {
createEditor();
}
});
function createEditor() {
StackExchange.prepareEditor({
heartbeatType: 'answer',
autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader: {
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
},
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
});
}
});
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f1675038%2fminimal-model-of-zf-with-0-sharp%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
1 Answer
1
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
up vote
3
down vote
accepted
Yes, the minimal such model is $L[0^sharp]$. This model can be built by stages, just as $L$, starting with the empty set, taking unions at limit stages, and at each successor stage $alpha+1$ taking the collection of subsets of $L_alpha[0^sharp]$ definable in $(L_alpha[0^sharp],in,0^sharp)$ from parameters. Here, $0^sharp$ can be thought of as a set of natural numbers, and definability is in the language of set theory with one additional predicate.
Note that for each finite $n$, $L_n[0^sharp]=L_n$ (that is, the universes of both structures coincide) and so $L_omega[0^sharp]=L_omega$. However, $0^sharp$ is now definable at this stage (as the set of numbers satisfying the new predicate), so $0^sharpin L[0^sharp]$.
This is not quite enough. Let $varphi(x)$ be the formula in the language of set theory stating that $x$ is $0^sharp$, i.e., stating that $x$ is the unique EM blueprint satisfying the three indiscernibility conditions listed in section 9 of
MR1994835 (2004f:03092) Kanamori, Akihiro. The higher infinite. Large cardinals in set theory from their beginnings. Second edition. Springer Monographs in Mathematics. Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 2003. xxii+536 pp. ISBN: 3-540-00384-3.
One should also check that $L[0^sharp]models varphi(0^sharp)$, and that whenever $M$ is an inner model and $Mmodelsvarphi(a)$ for some $a$, then $0^sharp$ exists in $V$ and $a=0^sharp$, so that $L[0^sharp]subseteq M$. This is essentially an absoluteness argument, but it is a bit technical so I will skip the details here. The point of proving this is that not only is $L[0^sharp]$ the smallest such model, but it knows it, in the sense that it satisfies $L[0^sharp]models V=L[0^sharp]$, and is contained in any inner model that believes in the existence of $0^sharp$.
One can prove more as well, for instance, $L[0^sharp]$ satisfies appropriate analogues of the fine structural properties of $L$, so it is not just the least model containing $0^sharp$, it is also a very well-behaved model. Naturally, the construction generalizes to more general sharps and other inner-model theoretic objects, although the absoluteness requirements become more involved.
add a comment |
up vote
3
down vote
accepted
Yes, the minimal such model is $L[0^sharp]$. This model can be built by stages, just as $L$, starting with the empty set, taking unions at limit stages, and at each successor stage $alpha+1$ taking the collection of subsets of $L_alpha[0^sharp]$ definable in $(L_alpha[0^sharp],in,0^sharp)$ from parameters. Here, $0^sharp$ can be thought of as a set of natural numbers, and definability is in the language of set theory with one additional predicate.
Note that for each finite $n$, $L_n[0^sharp]=L_n$ (that is, the universes of both structures coincide) and so $L_omega[0^sharp]=L_omega$. However, $0^sharp$ is now definable at this stage (as the set of numbers satisfying the new predicate), so $0^sharpin L[0^sharp]$.
This is not quite enough. Let $varphi(x)$ be the formula in the language of set theory stating that $x$ is $0^sharp$, i.e., stating that $x$ is the unique EM blueprint satisfying the three indiscernibility conditions listed in section 9 of
MR1994835 (2004f:03092) Kanamori, Akihiro. The higher infinite. Large cardinals in set theory from their beginnings. Second edition. Springer Monographs in Mathematics. Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 2003. xxii+536 pp. ISBN: 3-540-00384-3.
One should also check that $L[0^sharp]models varphi(0^sharp)$, and that whenever $M$ is an inner model and $Mmodelsvarphi(a)$ for some $a$, then $0^sharp$ exists in $V$ and $a=0^sharp$, so that $L[0^sharp]subseteq M$. This is essentially an absoluteness argument, but it is a bit technical so I will skip the details here. The point of proving this is that not only is $L[0^sharp]$ the smallest such model, but it knows it, in the sense that it satisfies $L[0^sharp]models V=L[0^sharp]$, and is contained in any inner model that believes in the existence of $0^sharp$.
One can prove more as well, for instance, $L[0^sharp]$ satisfies appropriate analogues of the fine structural properties of $L$, so it is not just the least model containing $0^sharp$, it is also a very well-behaved model. Naturally, the construction generalizes to more general sharps and other inner-model theoretic objects, although the absoluteness requirements become more involved.
add a comment |
up vote
3
down vote
accepted
up vote
3
down vote
accepted
Yes, the minimal such model is $L[0^sharp]$. This model can be built by stages, just as $L$, starting with the empty set, taking unions at limit stages, and at each successor stage $alpha+1$ taking the collection of subsets of $L_alpha[0^sharp]$ definable in $(L_alpha[0^sharp],in,0^sharp)$ from parameters. Here, $0^sharp$ can be thought of as a set of natural numbers, and definability is in the language of set theory with one additional predicate.
Note that for each finite $n$, $L_n[0^sharp]=L_n$ (that is, the universes of both structures coincide) and so $L_omega[0^sharp]=L_omega$. However, $0^sharp$ is now definable at this stage (as the set of numbers satisfying the new predicate), so $0^sharpin L[0^sharp]$.
This is not quite enough. Let $varphi(x)$ be the formula in the language of set theory stating that $x$ is $0^sharp$, i.e., stating that $x$ is the unique EM blueprint satisfying the three indiscernibility conditions listed in section 9 of
MR1994835 (2004f:03092) Kanamori, Akihiro. The higher infinite. Large cardinals in set theory from their beginnings. Second edition. Springer Monographs in Mathematics. Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 2003. xxii+536 pp. ISBN: 3-540-00384-3.
One should also check that $L[0^sharp]models varphi(0^sharp)$, and that whenever $M$ is an inner model and $Mmodelsvarphi(a)$ for some $a$, then $0^sharp$ exists in $V$ and $a=0^sharp$, so that $L[0^sharp]subseteq M$. This is essentially an absoluteness argument, but it is a bit technical so I will skip the details here. The point of proving this is that not only is $L[0^sharp]$ the smallest such model, but it knows it, in the sense that it satisfies $L[0^sharp]models V=L[0^sharp]$, and is contained in any inner model that believes in the existence of $0^sharp$.
One can prove more as well, for instance, $L[0^sharp]$ satisfies appropriate analogues of the fine structural properties of $L$, so it is not just the least model containing $0^sharp$, it is also a very well-behaved model. Naturally, the construction generalizes to more general sharps and other inner-model theoretic objects, although the absoluteness requirements become more involved.
Yes, the minimal such model is $L[0^sharp]$. This model can be built by stages, just as $L$, starting with the empty set, taking unions at limit stages, and at each successor stage $alpha+1$ taking the collection of subsets of $L_alpha[0^sharp]$ definable in $(L_alpha[0^sharp],in,0^sharp)$ from parameters. Here, $0^sharp$ can be thought of as a set of natural numbers, and definability is in the language of set theory with one additional predicate.
Note that for each finite $n$, $L_n[0^sharp]=L_n$ (that is, the universes of both structures coincide) and so $L_omega[0^sharp]=L_omega$. However, $0^sharp$ is now definable at this stage (as the set of numbers satisfying the new predicate), so $0^sharpin L[0^sharp]$.
This is not quite enough. Let $varphi(x)$ be the formula in the language of set theory stating that $x$ is $0^sharp$, i.e., stating that $x$ is the unique EM blueprint satisfying the three indiscernibility conditions listed in section 9 of
MR1994835 (2004f:03092) Kanamori, Akihiro. The higher infinite. Large cardinals in set theory from their beginnings. Second edition. Springer Monographs in Mathematics. Springer-Verlag, Berlin, 2003. xxii+536 pp. ISBN: 3-540-00384-3.
One should also check that $L[0^sharp]models varphi(0^sharp)$, and that whenever $M$ is an inner model and $Mmodelsvarphi(a)$ for some $a$, then $0^sharp$ exists in $V$ and $a=0^sharp$, so that $L[0^sharp]subseteq M$. This is essentially an absoluteness argument, but it is a bit technical so I will skip the details here. The point of proving this is that not only is $L[0^sharp]$ the smallest such model, but it knows it, in the sense that it satisfies $L[0^sharp]models V=L[0^sharp]$, and is contained in any inner model that believes in the existence of $0^sharp$.
One can prove more as well, for instance, $L[0^sharp]$ satisfies appropriate analogues of the fine structural properties of $L$, so it is not just the least model containing $0^sharp$, it is also a very well-behaved model. Naturally, the construction generalizes to more general sharps and other inner-model theoretic objects, although the absoluteness requirements become more involved.
answered Nov 27 at 18:32
Andrés E. Caicedo
64.7k8158246
64.7k8158246
add a comment |
add a comment |
Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!
- Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!
But avoid …
- Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.
- Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.
Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.
To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.
Some of your past answers have not been well-received, and you're in danger of being blocked from answering.
Please pay close attention to the following guidance:
- Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!
But avoid …
- Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.
- Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.
To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f1675038%2fminimal-model-of-zf-with-0-sharp%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
4
Sure. The model is denoted $L[0^sharp]$. You mimic the construction of $L$, but allow in your language a predicate for $0^sharp$ (understood as a set of numbers).
– Andrés E. Caicedo
Feb 28 '16 at 0:18
Isn't $L(0sharp)$ smaller?
– Alon Navon
Feb 28 '16 at 0:26
4
We have $L[0^sharp] = L(0^sharp)$: In general, for any given set $A$, we have $L[A] subseteq L(A)$ with equalitiy if and only if $A cap L[A] = A$. Since $0^sharp$ may be regarded as a subset of $omega$, we have $0^sharp subseteq L subseteq L[0^sharp]$ and thus the claimed equality.
– Stefan Mesken
Feb 28 '16 at 0:38
1
@Stefan Thank you very much, I got my relative constructibility all mixed up, and you cleared a lot. :) This means in essence that we can define a "sharp" sequence. $L_0 = L$, $L_1 = L[0^sharp]$, $L_2 = L[0^{sharpsharp}]$, etc... Just wondering whether there is any use for this? Any other nice properties that make these "L's" "L-ish"?
– Alon Navon
Feb 28 '16 at 0:49
3
Well, $L[A]$ is similar to $L$ in a lot of ways - a major reason for this is, that the usual condensation lemma generalizes to $L[A]$ (which allows us to prove $operatorname{GCH}$, $Diamond_kappa$, $square_kappa$, ... on a "tail segment" of $L[A]$).
– Stefan Mesken
Feb 28 '16 at 1:19