Sum/Product of two natural numbers is a natural number
$begingroup$
I wanted to prove that the sum and the product of two natural numbers is a natural number. Intuitively it's clear to my why that is true, however I couldn't prove it.
So our lecturer first defined what an inductive set is. Then he defined the Natural numbers as the intersection of all inductive sets. Then we proved the induction principle and $forall n in mathbb{N} , 1leq n$ .
So this is the information we have so far. But I am having difficulty proving that the sum/product of two natural numbers is a natural number. Can someone give me a clue how to prove this?
I am trying to prove this with the definition of a Natural numbers, but it's not working so far...
Thank you.
set-theory natural-numbers
$endgroup$
|
show 5 more comments
$begingroup$
I wanted to prove that the sum and the product of two natural numbers is a natural number. Intuitively it's clear to my why that is true, however I couldn't prove it.
So our lecturer first defined what an inductive set is. Then he defined the Natural numbers as the intersection of all inductive sets. Then we proved the induction principle and $forall n in mathbb{N} , 1leq n$ .
So this is the information we have so far. But I am having difficulty proving that the sum/product of two natural numbers is a natural number. Can someone give me a clue how to prove this?
I am trying to prove this with the definition of a Natural numbers, but it's not working so far...
Thank you.
set-theory natural-numbers
$endgroup$
1
$begingroup$
First you need the definition of addition and multiplication. Then prove by induction for any fixed $minmathbb{N}$ that ${ninmathbb{N} : n+m inmathbb{N}} = mathbb{N}$ (and similarly for the product).
$endgroup$
– Daniel Fischer♦
Oct 9 '14 at 13:33
$begingroup$
Hi Daniel, can you verify this proof? Proof: Let there be $m in mathbb{N}$. We will define the set I={$n in mathbb{N} | n+m in mathbb{N}$ } So we want to prove that $ I = mathbb{N}$ , from the definition of I we derive $I subset mathbb{N}$ so we have to prove that $mathbb{N} subset I $ . We will prove this with induction. Basis for the induction: n=1 . Since $m in mathbb{N}$ and $mathbb{N}$ is inductive, $m+1 in mathbb{N}$ and therefore $1 in I$. Induction Hyp:$n in I$ , we will prove that $n+1 in I$ Induct Step: If $n in I$ then $n+m in mathbb{N}$ since $mathbb{N}$ is
$endgroup$
– Charles Carmichael
Oct 9 '14 at 13:57
$begingroup$
inductive $n+m+1 in mathbb{N}$ therefore $n+1 in I$ and therefore $I=mathbb{N}$, as desired. Is this correct? Thank you.
$endgroup$
– Charles Carmichael
Oct 9 '14 at 14:01
$begingroup$
@DavidC You need to tag him, otherwise he won't get the notification of your comment.
$endgroup$
– Vincenzo Oliva
Oct 11 '14 at 9:24
1
$begingroup$
I have added (set-theory) tag, since the question is about set-theoretical definition of natural numbers (as the smallest inductive set) based on Axiom of Infinity.
$endgroup$
– Martin Sleziak
Feb 1 '15 at 11:40
|
show 5 more comments
$begingroup$
I wanted to prove that the sum and the product of two natural numbers is a natural number. Intuitively it's clear to my why that is true, however I couldn't prove it.
So our lecturer first defined what an inductive set is. Then he defined the Natural numbers as the intersection of all inductive sets. Then we proved the induction principle and $forall n in mathbb{N} , 1leq n$ .
So this is the information we have so far. But I am having difficulty proving that the sum/product of two natural numbers is a natural number. Can someone give me a clue how to prove this?
I am trying to prove this with the definition of a Natural numbers, but it's not working so far...
Thank you.
set-theory natural-numbers
$endgroup$
I wanted to prove that the sum and the product of two natural numbers is a natural number. Intuitively it's clear to my why that is true, however I couldn't prove it.
So our lecturer first defined what an inductive set is. Then he defined the Natural numbers as the intersection of all inductive sets. Then we proved the induction principle and $forall n in mathbb{N} , 1leq n$ .
So this is the information we have so far. But I am having difficulty proving that the sum/product of two natural numbers is a natural number. Can someone give me a clue how to prove this?
I am trying to prove this with the definition of a Natural numbers, but it's not working so far...
Thank you.
set-theory natural-numbers
set-theory natural-numbers
edited Feb 1 '15 at 11:38
Martin Sleziak
44.7k9117272
44.7k9117272
asked Oct 9 '14 at 13:29
Charles CarmichaelCharles Carmichael
30917
30917
1
$begingroup$
First you need the definition of addition and multiplication. Then prove by induction for any fixed $minmathbb{N}$ that ${ninmathbb{N} : n+m inmathbb{N}} = mathbb{N}$ (and similarly for the product).
$endgroup$
– Daniel Fischer♦
Oct 9 '14 at 13:33
$begingroup$
Hi Daniel, can you verify this proof? Proof: Let there be $m in mathbb{N}$. We will define the set I={$n in mathbb{N} | n+m in mathbb{N}$ } So we want to prove that $ I = mathbb{N}$ , from the definition of I we derive $I subset mathbb{N}$ so we have to prove that $mathbb{N} subset I $ . We will prove this with induction. Basis for the induction: n=1 . Since $m in mathbb{N}$ and $mathbb{N}$ is inductive, $m+1 in mathbb{N}$ and therefore $1 in I$. Induction Hyp:$n in I$ , we will prove that $n+1 in I$ Induct Step: If $n in I$ then $n+m in mathbb{N}$ since $mathbb{N}$ is
$endgroup$
– Charles Carmichael
Oct 9 '14 at 13:57
$begingroup$
inductive $n+m+1 in mathbb{N}$ therefore $n+1 in I$ and therefore $I=mathbb{N}$, as desired. Is this correct? Thank you.
$endgroup$
– Charles Carmichael
Oct 9 '14 at 14:01
$begingroup$
@DavidC You need to tag him, otherwise he won't get the notification of your comment.
$endgroup$
– Vincenzo Oliva
Oct 11 '14 at 9:24
1
$begingroup$
I have added (set-theory) tag, since the question is about set-theoretical definition of natural numbers (as the smallest inductive set) based on Axiom of Infinity.
$endgroup$
– Martin Sleziak
Feb 1 '15 at 11:40
|
show 5 more comments
1
$begingroup$
First you need the definition of addition and multiplication. Then prove by induction for any fixed $minmathbb{N}$ that ${ninmathbb{N} : n+m inmathbb{N}} = mathbb{N}$ (and similarly for the product).
$endgroup$
– Daniel Fischer♦
Oct 9 '14 at 13:33
$begingroup$
Hi Daniel, can you verify this proof? Proof: Let there be $m in mathbb{N}$. We will define the set I={$n in mathbb{N} | n+m in mathbb{N}$ } So we want to prove that $ I = mathbb{N}$ , from the definition of I we derive $I subset mathbb{N}$ so we have to prove that $mathbb{N} subset I $ . We will prove this with induction. Basis for the induction: n=1 . Since $m in mathbb{N}$ and $mathbb{N}$ is inductive, $m+1 in mathbb{N}$ and therefore $1 in I$. Induction Hyp:$n in I$ , we will prove that $n+1 in I$ Induct Step: If $n in I$ then $n+m in mathbb{N}$ since $mathbb{N}$ is
$endgroup$
– Charles Carmichael
Oct 9 '14 at 13:57
$begingroup$
inductive $n+m+1 in mathbb{N}$ therefore $n+1 in I$ and therefore $I=mathbb{N}$, as desired. Is this correct? Thank you.
$endgroup$
– Charles Carmichael
Oct 9 '14 at 14:01
$begingroup$
@DavidC You need to tag him, otherwise he won't get the notification of your comment.
$endgroup$
– Vincenzo Oliva
Oct 11 '14 at 9:24
1
$begingroup$
I have added (set-theory) tag, since the question is about set-theoretical definition of natural numbers (as the smallest inductive set) based on Axiom of Infinity.
$endgroup$
– Martin Sleziak
Feb 1 '15 at 11:40
1
1
$begingroup$
First you need the definition of addition and multiplication. Then prove by induction for any fixed $minmathbb{N}$ that ${ninmathbb{N} : n+m inmathbb{N}} = mathbb{N}$ (and similarly for the product).
$endgroup$
– Daniel Fischer♦
Oct 9 '14 at 13:33
$begingroup$
First you need the definition of addition and multiplication. Then prove by induction for any fixed $minmathbb{N}$ that ${ninmathbb{N} : n+m inmathbb{N}} = mathbb{N}$ (and similarly for the product).
$endgroup$
– Daniel Fischer♦
Oct 9 '14 at 13:33
$begingroup$
Hi Daniel, can you verify this proof? Proof: Let there be $m in mathbb{N}$. We will define the set I={$n in mathbb{N} | n+m in mathbb{N}$ } So we want to prove that $ I = mathbb{N}$ , from the definition of I we derive $I subset mathbb{N}$ so we have to prove that $mathbb{N} subset I $ . We will prove this with induction. Basis for the induction: n=1 . Since $m in mathbb{N}$ and $mathbb{N}$ is inductive, $m+1 in mathbb{N}$ and therefore $1 in I$. Induction Hyp:$n in I$ , we will prove that $n+1 in I$ Induct Step: If $n in I$ then $n+m in mathbb{N}$ since $mathbb{N}$ is
$endgroup$
– Charles Carmichael
Oct 9 '14 at 13:57
$begingroup$
Hi Daniel, can you verify this proof? Proof: Let there be $m in mathbb{N}$. We will define the set I={$n in mathbb{N} | n+m in mathbb{N}$ } So we want to prove that $ I = mathbb{N}$ , from the definition of I we derive $I subset mathbb{N}$ so we have to prove that $mathbb{N} subset I $ . We will prove this with induction. Basis for the induction: n=1 . Since $m in mathbb{N}$ and $mathbb{N}$ is inductive, $m+1 in mathbb{N}$ and therefore $1 in I$. Induction Hyp:$n in I$ , we will prove that $n+1 in I$ Induct Step: If $n in I$ then $n+m in mathbb{N}$ since $mathbb{N}$ is
$endgroup$
– Charles Carmichael
Oct 9 '14 at 13:57
$begingroup$
inductive $n+m+1 in mathbb{N}$ therefore $n+1 in I$ and therefore $I=mathbb{N}$, as desired. Is this correct? Thank you.
$endgroup$
– Charles Carmichael
Oct 9 '14 at 14:01
$begingroup$
inductive $n+m+1 in mathbb{N}$ therefore $n+1 in I$ and therefore $I=mathbb{N}$, as desired. Is this correct? Thank you.
$endgroup$
– Charles Carmichael
Oct 9 '14 at 14:01
$begingroup$
@DavidC You need to tag him, otherwise he won't get the notification of your comment.
$endgroup$
– Vincenzo Oliva
Oct 11 '14 at 9:24
$begingroup$
@DavidC You need to tag him, otherwise he won't get the notification of your comment.
$endgroup$
– Vincenzo Oliva
Oct 11 '14 at 9:24
1
1
$begingroup$
I have added (set-theory) tag, since the question is about set-theoretical definition of natural numbers (as the smallest inductive set) based on Axiom of Infinity.
$endgroup$
– Martin Sleziak
Feb 1 '15 at 11:40
$begingroup$
I have added (set-theory) tag, since the question is about set-theoretical definition of natural numbers (as the smallest inductive set) based on Axiom of Infinity.
$endgroup$
– Martin Sleziak
Feb 1 '15 at 11:40
|
show 5 more comments
2 Answers
2
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
How are sum/product operations in $mathbb{N}$ defined in your context?
Let $n,minmathbb{N}$.
Write $s(n)=ncup {n}$. Observe $s(n)inmathbb{N}$ by definition of inductive set, and recall
$$mneq 0 implies exists linmathbb{N} big(m=s(l)big).$$
Both addition and multiplication are binary operations in $mathbb{N}$ defined recursively as follows:
Addition (or "sum"):
- If $m=0$, then $n+ m := m$
- If $mneq 0$, then $n+ m := s(n+l)$
Multiplication (or "product"):
- If $m=0$, then $ncdot m = 0$
- If $mneq 0$, then $ncdot m = ncdot l + n$
Thus, by this definition and using induction, the result of both sum and product are also natural numbers.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
The OP stated
So our lecturer first defined what an inductive set is. Then he defined the Natural numbers as the intersection of all inductive sets. Then we proved the induction principle and $forall n in mathbb{N} , , 1 le n$.
I think the OP meant to say $forall n in mathbb{N} , , 0 le n$, but in any case the following discussion will be instructive.
So we are starting with the von Neumann ordinal $omega = mathbb N$ (see the wiki article Axiom of infinity).
With this setup a binary operation called addition can be defined mapping an ordered pair in $(m,n) in mathbb{N} times mathbb{N}$ to another natural number, $m + n$.
With this setup a binary operation called mulitiplication can be defined mapping an ordered pair in $(m,n) in mathbb{N} times mathbb{N}$ to another natural number, $m * n$.
Once you define these operations, you have to prove (abstractly) that these operations satisfy all the properties of addition and multiplication that you learned in elementary school (for example, that multiplication distributes over addition).
We conclude this by defining addition.
If $m,n in mathbb N$ they can be viewed as ordinals (well-ordered sets) and we can define addition, up to an isomorphism of well-ordered sets. But the following is also true:
Theorem: Any two ordinals $X$, $Y$ are comparable, in the sense that either $X = Y$, or $X$ is an initial segment of $Y$ , or $Y$ is an initial segment of $X$.
The OP has to show that if they add the ordinals $m$ and $n$ then $m + n$ is an initial segment of $mathbb N$. Since every (proper) initial segment of $mathbb N$ has a greatest element $s$, the mapping $m + n mapsto s$ is well-defined.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Or maybe this takes place in a real analysis course, where commonly $Bbb N$ is just the intersection of all inductive subsets of $Bbb R$, where inductive means $1in A$ and $ain Ato a+1in A$. So maybe this has nothing to do with ordinals, and everything to do with induction. Not to mention that you completely sidestep the question and just say "Well, we can define addition and multiplication and then prove they satisfy what we want them to satisfy". Well, isn't this the whole point of this question?
$endgroup$
– Asaf Karagila♦
Jan 9 at 11:09
add a comment |
Your Answer
StackExchange.ifUsing("editor", function () {
return StackExchange.using("mathjaxEditing", function () {
StackExchange.MarkdownEditor.creationCallbacks.add(function (editor, postfix) {
StackExchange.mathjaxEditing.prepareWmdForMathJax(editor, postfix, [["$", "$"], ["\\(","\\)"]]);
});
});
}, "mathjax-editing");
StackExchange.ready(function() {
var channelOptions = {
tags: "".split(" "),
id: "69"
};
initTagRenderer("".split(" "), "".split(" "), channelOptions);
StackExchange.using("externalEditor", function() {
// Have to fire editor after snippets, if snippets enabled
if (StackExchange.settings.snippets.snippetsEnabled) {
StackExchange.using("snippets", function() {
createEditor();
});
}
else {
createEditor();
}
});
function createEditor() {
StackExchange.prepareEditor({
heartbeatType: 'answer',
autoActivateHeartbeat: false,
convertImagesToLinks: true,
noModals: true,
showLowRepImageUploadWarning: true,
reputationToPostImages: 10,
bindNavPrevention: true,
postfix: "",
imageUploader: {
brandingHtml: "Powered by u003ca class="icon-imgur-white" href="https://imgur.com/"u003eu003c/au003e",
contentPolicyHtml: "User contributions licensed under u003ca href="https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/"u003ecc by-sa 3.0 with attribution requiredu003c/au003e u003ca href="https://stackoverflow.com/legal/content-policy"u003e(content policy)u003c/au003e",
allowUrls: true
},
noCode: true, onDemand: true,
discardSelector: ".discard-answer"
,immediatelyShowMarkdownHelp:true
});
}
});
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f965178%2fsum-product-of-two-natural-numbers-is-a-natural-number%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
2 Answers
2
active
oldest
votes
2 Answers
2
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
active
oldest
votes
$begingroup$
How are sum/product operations in $mathbb{N}$ defined in your context?
Let $n,minmathbb{N}$.
Write $s(n)=ncup {n}$. Observe $s(n)inmathbb{N}$ by definition of inductive set, and recall
$$mneq 0 implies exists linmathbb{N} big(m=s(l)big).$$
Both addition and multiplication are binary operations in $mathbb{N}$ defined recursively as follows:
Addition (or "sum"):
- If $m=0$, then $n+ m := m$
- If $mneq 0$, then $n+ m := s(n+l)$
Multiplication (or "product"):
- If $m=0$, then $ncdot m = 0$
- If $mneq 0$, then $ncdot m = ncdot l + n$
Thus, by this definition and using induction, the result of both sum and product are also natural numbers.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
How are sum/product operations in $mathbb{N}$ defined in your context?
Let $n,minmathbb{N}$.
Write $s(n)=ncup {n}$. Observe $s(n)inmathbb{N}$ by definition of inductive set, and recall
$$mneq 0 implies exists linmathbb{N} big(m=s(l)big).$$
Both addition and multiplication are binary operations in $mathbb{N}$ defined recursively as follows:
Addition (or "sum"):
- If $m=0$, then $n+ m := m$
- If $mneq 0$, then $n+ m := s(n+l)$
Multiplication (or "product"):
- If $m=0$, then $ncdot m = 0$
- If $mneq 0$, then $ncdot m = ncdot l + n$
Thus, by this definition and using induction, the result of both sum and product are also natural numbers.
$endgroup$
add a comment |
$begingroup$
How are sum/product operations in $mathbb{N}$ defined in your context?
Let $n,minmathbb{N}$.
Write $s(n)=ncup {n}$. Observe $s(n)inmathbb{N}$ by definition of inductive set, and recall
$$mneq 0 implies exists linmathbb{N} big(m=s(l)big).$$
Both addition and multiplication are binary operations in $mathbb{N}$ defined recursively as follows:
Addition (or "sum"):
- If $m=0$, then $n+ m := m$
- If $mneq 0$, then $n+ m := s(n+l)$
Multiplication (or "product"):
- If $m=0$, then $ncdot m = 0$
- If $mneq 0$, then $ncdot m = ncdot l + n$
Thus, by this definition and using induction, the result of both sum and product are also natural numbers.
$endgroup$
How are sum/product operations in $mathbb{N}$ defined in your context?
Let $n,minmathbb{N}$.
Write $s(n)=ncup {n}$. Observe $s(n)inmathbb{N}$ by definition of inductive set, and recall
$$mneq 0 implies exists linmathbb{N} big(m=s(l)big).$$
Both addition and multiplication are binary operations in $mathbb{N}$ defined recursively as follows:
Addition (or "sum"):
- If $m=0$, then $n+ m := m$
- If $mneq 0$, then $n+ m := s(n+l)$
Multiplication (or "product"):
- If $m=0$, then $ncdot m = 0$
- If $mneq 0$, then $ncdot m = ncdot l + n$
Thus, by this definition and using induction, the result of both sum and product are also natural numbers.
edited Dec 6 '18 at 17:06
answered Dec 5 '18 at 18:27
Dr PotatoDr Potato
394
394
add a comment |
add a comment |
$begingroup$
The OP stated
So our lecturer first defined what an inductive set is. Then he defined the Natural numbers as the intersection of all inductive sets. Then we proved the induction principle and $forall n in mathbb{N} , , 1 le n$.
I think the OP meant to say $forall n in mathbb{N} , , 0 le n$, but in any case the following discussion will be instructive.
So we are starting with the von Neumann ordinal $omega = mathbb N$ (see the wiki article Axiom of infinity).
With this setup a binary operation called addition can be defined mapping an ordered pair in $(m,n) in mathbb{N} times mathbb{N}$ to another natural number, $m + n$.
With this setup a binary operation called mulitiplication can be defined mapping an ordered pair in $(m,n) in mathbb{N} times mathbb{N}$ to another natural number, $m * n$.
Once you define these operations, you have to prove (abstractly) that these operations satisfy all the properties of addition and multiplication that you learned in elementary school (for example, that multiplication distributes over addition).
We conclude this by defining addition.
If $m,n in mathbb N$ they can be viewed as ordinals (well-ordered sets) and we can define addition, up to an isomorphism of well-ordered sets. But the following is also true:
Theorem: Any two ordinals $X$, $Y$ are comparable, in the sense that either $X = Y$, or $X$ is an initial segment of $Y$ , or $Y$ is an initial segment of $X$.
The OP has to show that if they add the ordinals $m$ and $n$ then $m + n$ is an initial segment of $mathbb N$. Since every (proper) initial segment of $mathbb N$ has a greatest element $s$, the mapping $m + n mapsto s$ is well-defined.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Or maybe this takes place in a real analysis course, where commonly $Bbb N$ is just the intersection of all inductive subsets of $Bbb R$, where inductive means $1in A$ and $ain Ato a+1in A$. So maybe this has nothing to do with ordinals, and everything to do with induction. Not to mention that you completely sidestep the question and just say "Well, we can define addition and multiplication and then prove they satisfy what we want them to satisfy". Well, isn't this the whole point of this question?
$endgroup$
– Asaf Karagila♦
Jan 9 at 11:09
add a comment |
$begingroup$
The OP stated
So our lecturer first defined what an inductive set is. Then he defined the Natural numbers as the intersection of all inductive sets. Then we proved the induction principle and $forall n in mathbb{N} , , 1 le n$.
I think the OP meant to say $forall n in mathbb{N} , , 0 le n$, but in any case the following discussion will be instructive.
So we are starting with the von Neumann ordinal $omega = mathbb N$ (see the wiki article Axiom of infinity).
With this setup a binary operation called addition can be defined mapping an ordered pair in $(m,n) in mathbb{N} times mathbb{N}$ to another natural number, $m + n$.
With this setup a binary operation called mulitiplication can be defined mapping an ordered pair in $(m,n) in mathbb{N} times mathbb{N}$ to another natural number, $m * n$.
Once you define these operations, you have to prove (abstractly) that these operations satisfy all the properties of addition and multiplication that you learned in elementary school (for example, that multiplication distributes over addition).
We conclude this by defining addition.
If $m,n in mathbb N$ they can be viewed as ordinals (well-ordered sets) and we can define addition, up to an isomorphism of well-ordered sets. But the following is also true:
Theorem: Any two ordinals $X$, $Y$ are comparable, in the sense that either $X = Y$, or $X$ is an initial segment of $Y$ , or $Y$ is an initial segment of $X$.
The OP has to show that if they add the ordinals $m$ and $n$ then $m + n$ is an initial segment of $mathbb N$. Since every (proper) initial segment of $mathbb N$ has a greatest element $s$, the mapping $m + n mapsto s$ is well-defined.
$endgroup$
$begingroup$
Or maybe this takes place in a real analysis course, where commonly $Bbb N$ is just the intersection of all inductive subsets of $Bbb R$, where inductive means $1in A$ and $ain Ato a+1in A$. So maybe this has nothing to do with ordinals, and everything to do with induction. Not to mention that you completely sidestep the question and just say "Well, we can define addition and multiplication and then prove they satisfy what we want them to satisfy". Well, isn't this the whole point of this question?
$endgroup$
– Asaf Karagila♦
Jan 9 at 11:09
add a comment |
$begingroup$
The OP stated
So our lecturer first defined what an inductive set is. Then he defined the Natural numbers as the intersection of all inductive sets. Then we proved the induction principle and $forall n in mathbb{N} , , 1 le n$.
I think the OP meant to say $forall n in mathbb{N} , , 0 le n$, but in any case the following discussion will be instructive.
So we are starting with the von Neumann ordinal $omega = mathbb N$ (see the wiki article Axiom of infinity).
With this setup a binary operation called addition can be defined mapping an ordered pair in $(m,n) in mathbb{N} times mathbb{N}$ to another natural number, $m + n$.
With this setup a binary operation called mulitiplication can be defined mapping an ordered pair in $(m,n) in mathbb{N} times mathbb{N}$ to another natural number, $m * n$.
Once you define these operations, you have to prove (abstractly) that these operations satisfy all the properties of addition and multiplication that you learned in elementary school (for example, that multiplication distributes over addition).
We conclude this by defining addition.
If $m,n in mathbb N$ they can be viewed as ordinals (well-ordered sets) and we can define addition, up to an isomorphism of well-ordered sets. But the following is also true:
Theorem: Any two ordinals $X$, $Y$ are comparable, in the sense that either $X = Y$, or $X$ is an initial segment of $Y$ , or $Y$ is an initial segment of $X$.
The OP has to show that if they add the ordinals $m$ and $n$ then $m + n$ is an initial segment of $mathbb N$. Since every (proper) initial segment of $mathbb N$ has a greatest element $s$, the mapping $m + n mapsto s$ is well-defined.
$endgroup$
The OP stated
So our lecturer first defined what an inductive set is. Then he defined the Natural numbers as the intersection of all inductive sets. Then we proved the induction principle and $forall n in mathbb{N} , , 1 le n$.
I think the OP meant to say $forall n in mathbb{N} , , 0 le n$, but in any case the following discussion will be instructive.
So we are starting with the von Neumann ordinal $omega = mathbb N$ (see the wiki article Axiom of infinity).
With this setup a binary operation called addition can be defined mapping an ordered pair in $(m,n) in mathbb{N} times mathbb{N}$ to another natural number, $m + n$.
With this setup a binary operation called mulitiplication can be defined mapping an ordered pair in $(m,n) in mathbb{N} times mathbb{N}$ to another natural number, $m * n$.
Once you define these operations, you have to prove (abstractly) that these operations satisfy all the properties of addition and multiplication that you learned in elementary school (for example, that multiplication distributes over addition).
We conclude this by defining addition.
If $m,n in mathbb N$ they can be viewed as ordinals (well-ordered sets) and we can define addition, up to an isomorphism of well-ordered sets. But the following is also true:
Theorem: Any two ordinals $X$, $Y$ are comparable, in the sense that either $X = Y$, or $X$ is an initial segment of $Y$ , or $Y$ is an initial segment of $X$.
The OP has to show that if they add the ordinals $m$ and $n$ then $m + n$ is an initial segment of $mathbb N$. Since every (proper) initial segment of $mathbb N$ has a greatest element $s$, the mapping $m + n mapsto s$ is well-defined.
answered Jan 9 at 11:05
CopyPasteItCopyPasteIt
4,1161628
4,1161628
$begingroup$
Or maybe this takes place in a real analysis course, where commonly $Bbb N$ is just the intersection of all inductive subsets of $Bbb R$, where inductive means $1in A$ and $ain Ato a+1in A$. So maybe this has nothing to do with ordinals, and everything to do with induction. Not to mention that you completely sidestep the question and just say "Well, we can define addition and multiplication and then prove they satisfy what we want them to satisfy". Well, isn't this the whole point of this question?
$endgroup$
– Asaf Karagila♦
Jan 9 at 11:09
add a comment |
$begingroup$
Or maybe this takes place in a real analysis course, where commonly $Bbb N$ is just the intersection of all inductive subsets of $Bbb R$, where inductive means $1in A$ and $ain Ato a+1in A$. So maybe this has nothing to do with ordinals, and everything to do with induction. Not to mention that you completely sidestep the question and just say "Well, we can define addition and multiplication and then prove they satisfy what we want them to satisfy". Well, isn't this the whole point of this question?
$endgroup$
– Asaf Karagila♦
Jan 9 at 11:09
$begingroup$
Or maybe this takes place in a real analysis course, where commonly $Bbb N$ is just the intersection of all inductive subsets of $Bbb R$, where inductive means $1in A$ and $ain Ato a+1in A$. So maybe this has nothing to do with ordinals, and everything to do with induction. Not to mention that you completely sidestep the question and just say "Well, we can define addition and multiplication and then prove they satisfy what we want them to satisfy". Well, isn't this the whole point of this question?
$endgroup$
– Asaf Karagila♦
Jan 9 at 11:09
$begingroup$
Or maybe this takes place in a real analysis course, where commonly $Bbb N$ is just the intersection of all inductive subsets of $Bbb R$, where inductive means $1in A$ and $ain Ato a+1in A$. So maybe this has nothing to do with ordinals, and everything to do with induction. Not to mention that you completely sidestep the question and just say "Well, we can define addition and multiplication and then prove they satisfy what we want them to satisfy". Well, isn't this the whole point of this question?
$endgroup$
– Asaf Karagila♦
Jan 9 at 11:09
add a comment |
Thanks for contributing an answer to Mathematics Stack Exchange!
- Please be sure to answer the question. Provide details and share your research!
But avoid …
- Asking for help, clarification, or responding to other answers.
- Making statements based on opinion; back them up with references or personal experience.
Use MathJax to format equations. MathJax reference.
To learn more, see our tips on writing great answers.
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
StackExchange.ready(
function () {
StackExchange.openid.initPostLogin('.new-post-login', 'https%3a%2f%2fmath.stackexchange.com%2fquestions%2f965178%2fsum-product-of-two-natural-numbers-is-a-natural-number%23new-answer', 'question_page');
}
);
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Sign up or log in
StackExchange.ready(function () {
StackExchange.helpers.onClickDraftSave('#login-link');
});
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Sign up using Google
Sign up using Facebook
Sign up using Email and Password
Post as a guest
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
Required, but never shown
1
$begingroup$
First you need the definition of addition and multiplication. Then prove by induction for any fixed $minmathbb{N}$ that ${ninmathbb{N} : n+m inmathbb{N}} = mathbb{N}$ (and similarly for the product).
$endgroup$
– Daniel Fischer♦
Oct 9 '14 at 13:33
$begingroup$
Hi Daniel, can you verify this proof? Proof: Let there be $m in mathbb{N}$. We will define the set I={$n in mathbb{N} | n+m in mathbb{N}$ } So we want to prove that $ I = mathbb{N}$ , from the definition of I we derive $I subset mathbb{N}$ so we have to prove that $mathbb{N} subset I $ . We will prove this with induction. Basis for the induction: n=1 . Since $m in mathbb{N}$ and $mathbb{N}$ is inductive, $m+1 in mathbb{N}$ and therefore $1 in I$. Induction Hyp:$n in I$ , we will prove that $n+1 in I$ Induct Step: If $n in I$ then $n+m in mathbb{N}$ since $mathbb{N}$ is
$endgroup$
– Charles Carmichael
Oct 9 '14 at 13:57
$begingroup$
inductive $n+m+1 in mathbb{N}$ therefore $n+1 in I$ and therefore $I=mathbb{N}$, as desired. Is this correct? Thank you.
$endgroup$
– Charles Carmichael
Oct 9 '14 at 14:01
$begingroup$
@DavidC You need to tag him, otherwise he won't get the notification of your comment.
$endgroup$
– Vincenzo Oliva
Oct 11 '14 at 9:24
1
$begingroup$
I have added (set-theory) tag, since the question is about set-theoretical definition of natural numbers (as the smallest inductive set) based on Axiom of Infinity.
$endgroup$
– Martin Sleziak
Feb 1 '15 at 11:40